Lara Scaglia

Kant´s Notion of a Transcendental Schema


Скачать книгу

cannot be considered as a mere sum of representations, because the condition required to have them lies exactly in their reference to a common unity distinguished from them:

      “[…] in order to have representations of external objects, an activity of judging or forming propositions is required, and that in order to be able to do the latter, an activity of distinguishing between the external thing, the representation, and one’s own self is required. […] it is the notion of something that we have to think in order to be able to explain representations of external objects. Without such a notion of the self, as distinct from the representations of other things, the possibility of forming propositions about the existence of external things could not even be entertained. This notion is a requirement of thought.” (Thiel 2018, pp. 70–71)

      More specifically, he explains this dualistic interactionism by means of two basic propositions:

      Against this background Tetens regards the schema perceptionis not only as something that mediates between sensibility and understanding, but also as the physical centre of unification of all the data of experience. Unfortunately, observation cannot inquire fully and completely the nature of these ideas. It is only possible to affirm that experience teaches that our organs are constituted by nerves, in which it is probable (but not observable), that a fluid matter or vital spirits flow. In his view, this process provides the physiological correlate or basis for ideas, which are therefore called “material ideas” - “materielle Ideen” - (Tetens 1777, I, p. vii, transl. L.S.). The existence of such ideas is postulated as reasonable hypothesis. What is important, however, is that material ideas, just like representations as they are observed through inner sense, need to be unified. That is precisely what the sensorium commune or the schema perceptionis does. The interpretation of schema as mediating function linking passivity and activity, senses and cognition opens out one path towards Kant’s epistemic use of the notion. But Tetens was not the author of this notion of schema: Darjes, as it has already been stressed, uses this noun in an epistemic sense also. Bonnet although he himself does not use the word ‘schema’, plays a relevant role as well in the ←39 | 40→development of the research on a middle function between understanding and sensibility and an equivalent or at least concept similar to ‘schema’ can be found in his work, namely sensorium commune.

      Kant might be accused of having disregarded the accounts of his predecessors concerning the notion of schemata. In the Critique of Pure Reason he makes several references to Plato, Aristotle, Bacon and Tetens, but none of these are devoted to the topic of schemata. However, Kant will build a doctrine of schemata whose meaning finds, in the Critique of Pure Reason, its greater epistemic and philosophical expression and complexity. It can be used as a main element for explaining the possibility of objective knowledge and the relation between sensibility and understanding. I shall show that Kant has the merit to have provided schemata with a definition (or definitions) and a precise role in his thought.←40 | 41→