Massimo Airoldi

Machine Habitus


Скачать книгу

algorithmic systems in their decision making. For instance, Netflix’s recommendation system is estimated to influence choice for ‘about 80% of hours streamed’, with ‘the remaining 20%’ coming ‘from search, which requires its own set of algorithms’ (Gomez-Uribe and Hunt 2015: 5). Similar figures can be found for other platforms, including Amazon, and they explain the spectacular marketing success of recommender algorithms (Celma 2010; Konstan and Riedl 2012; Ansari, Essegaier and Kohli 2000). Myriad feedback loops like the one sketched above constellate our digitally mediated existence, eventually producing self-reinforcement effects that translate into a reduced or increased exposure to specific types of content, selected based on past user behaviour (Bucher 2012a). By modulating the visibility of social media posts, micro-targeted ads or search results, autonomous systems not only mediate digital experiences, but ‘constitute’ them (Beer 2009), often by ‘nudging’ individual behaviours and opinions (Christin 2020; Darmody and Zwick 2020). What happens is that ‘the models analyze the world and the world responds to the models’ (Kitchin and Dodge 2011: 30). As a result, human cultures end up becoming algorithmic cultures (Striphas 2015).

      Critical research has mainly dealt with this ‘social power’ of algorithms as a one-way effect (Beer 2017), with the risk of putting forward forms of technological determinism – implicit, for instance, in most of the literature about filter bubbles (Bruns 2019: 24). Yet, recent studies show that the outputs of autonomous machines are actively negotiated and problematized by individuals (Velkova and Kaun 2019). Automated music recommendations or micro-targeted ads are not always effective at orienting the taste and consumption of platform users (Siles et al. 2020; Ruckenstein and Granroth 2020; Bucher 2017). Algorithms do not unidirectionally shape our datafied society. Rather, they intervene within it, taking part in situated socio-material interactions involving both human and non-human agents (Law 1990; D. Mackenzie 2019; Burr, Cristianini and Ladyman 2018; Orlikowski 2007; Rose and Jones 2005). Hence, the content of ‘algorithmic culture’ (Striphas 2015) is the emergent outcome of techno-social interactional dynamics. From this point of view, my deciding whether or not to click on a recommended book on Amazon represents an instance of human–machine interaction – which is, of course, heavily engineered to serve the commercial goals of platforms. Nonetheless, in this digitally mediated exchange, both the machine learning algorithm and I maintain relative margins of freedom. My reaction to recommendations will be immediately measured by the system, which will behave differently in our next encounter, also based on that feedback. On my end, I will perhaps discover new authors and titles thanks to this particular algorithm, or – as often happens – ignore its automated suggestions.

      These open questions about the culture in the code and the code in the culture are closely related. A second-order feedback loop is implicit here, one that overlooks all the countless interactions between algorithms and their users. It consists in the recursive mechanism through which ‘the social’ – with its varying cultural norms, institutions and social structures – is reproduced by the actions of its members, who collectively make society while simultaneously being made by it. If you forget about algorithms for a second, you will probably recognize here one of the foundational dilemmas of the social sciences, traditionally torn by the complexities of micro–macro dynamics and cultural change (Coleman 1994; Giddens 1984; Bourdieu 1989a; Strand and Lizardo 2017). In fact, while it can be argued that social structures like class, gender or ethnicity ‘exercise a frequently “despotic” effect on the behaviour of social actors’ – producing statistically observable regularities in all social domains, from political preferences to musical taste – these very same structures ‘are the product of human action’ (Boudon and Bourricaud 2003: 10). Since the times of Weber and Durkheim, sociologists have attempted to explain this paradox, largely by prioritizing one out of two main opposing views, which can be summarized as follows: on the one side, the idea that social structures powerfully condition and determine individual lives; on the other, the individualistic view of a free and agentic subject that makes society from below.

      Why do individuals born and raised under similar social conditions happen to have almost identical lifestyles, ways of walking and speaking, modes of thinking about and acting within the world? Why do unskilled workers and highly educated bourgeois have such different ideas about what makes a song ‘bad’, a piece of furniture ‘nice’, a TV show ‘disgusting’, a behaviour ‘inappropriate’, a person ‘valuable’? How come that the everyday practices of women and men, Algerian farmers and French colonialists, dominated and dominators, end up jointly reproducing material and symbolic inequalities? These are some of the crucial questions Bourdieu asked in his research. All point to a general sociological dilemma, and have a common theoretical solution: ‘So why is social life so regular and so predictable? If external structures do not mechanically constrain action, what then gives it its pattern? The concept of habitus provides part of the answer’ (Bourdieu and Wacquant 1992: 18).