Скачать книгу

The key advantage of randomisation is that it should capture all possibly relevant factors in the population and the random assignment to treatment and control groups should ensure that they are present to an equal degree in both groups.

      The problem, as we shall see in Chapter 8, concerns what the relevant population actually is. The problem is acute in EER because we cannot make assumptions about population uniformity even across urban districts (Webber and Butler 2007), let alone regions, nations and cultures. In other words, context is extremely important in determining what the relevant population is going to be. An RCT which tests a particular teaching intervention can be shown to be likely to be effective in a particular context. We can be reasonably confident that ‘it works here’ (Cartwright and Hardie 2012).

      We cannot infer from the fact that it works here to the likelihood of its working elsewhere because we may not know the background conditions which enabled it to work here and which might militate it working somewhere else. The relevant explanatory field for the RCT is the particular context (local authority, jurisdiction or whatever) in which the intervention was successfully trialled. Working stepwise we can trial it in other contexts, not knowing whether these should constitute different explanatory fields, but we cannot always expect the same result because other factors may be in operation in other contexts. They may operate directly on teacher effectiveness or they may have an effect on those factors that are known to have such an effect. In either case, it may be that we are unable to extrapolate ‘what works’ from one context to another, and we will have to proceed by trial and error in determining the sense of explanatory fields.

       All We Need Is Commonsense

      This is important as teachers need not only powers of situational judgement but also the ability to act on the basis of empirical evidence. If this evidence can be concentrated into a form of instinctive judgement as Burke suggests, then it is a potentially powerful professional tool. Unfortunately, however, the very scepticism that the advocate of common sense deploys against EER can justifiably be directed with even more force at the deliverances of this form of common sense. To see this, consider a famous quotation from Keynes concerning the ‘common sense’ of businessmen:

      Practical men, who believe themselves to be quite exempt from any intellectual influences, are usually the slaves of some defunct economist. Madmen in authority, who hear voices in the air, are distilling their frenzy from some academic scribbler of a few years back. (Keynes 1936, p. 383)

      Quite independently, Gramsci had developed a similar account of how beliefs developed in ‘high culture’ or within science or systematic enquiry come to be distilled and often distorted into a form of folk belief. Like Keynes, he thought that far from being a sure guide to action, such beliefs were often irrational. Thus he writes of common sense that

      its most fundamental characteristic is that it is a conception which, even in the brain of one individual, is fragmentary, incoherent and inconsequential, in conformity with the social and cultural position of the masses whose philosophy it is. (Gramsci 1971, p. 419)

      How are these considerations relevant to the EER sceptic? One version of the EER sceptic prides himself on the primacy of common sense and the irrelevance of EER. But he cannot deny that the practice of EER takes place and that its results are disseminated and often influential. The provenance of beliefs that may have had an origin in EER are often dimly, if at all, understood. The history of EER over the last century is full of examples of the assumptions and results of EER which have contributed to popular and professional belief about educational potential and achievement: IQ theory, developmental theories, verbal deficit theories and psycholinguistic accounts of how children learn to read and write – to name but a few of the more prominent of these.

      Thus, EER has a powerful (and often malign) effect on educational practice through a dysfunctional mode of dissemination into the profession. Craft theories of teaching (Winch, C. 2017) are particularly susceptible as they rely so heavily on an uncritical and untheorised conception of common sense which fails to separate out the various elements described above.

      The conclusion of this part of the discussion is that the advocate of EER scepticism has completely undermined the ground on which he stands by failing to take account of the fact that even if EER is ignored and dismissed as irrelevant it often re-appears in the often incoherent but strongly held views of teachers. The result of this is that ‘craft knowledge’ ends up having a profound and undesirable effect on educational practice through being a distorted and partial version of a theory which may well not have been true in the first place.

       Education Is Value-laden and Hence Cannot Be Studied Empirically in a Value-neutral Form