Группа авторов

A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value


Скачать книгу

points on this topic with reference to a schematic, imaginary example, the stipulated features of which are not subject to empirical dispute.

      Imagine, then, a case where a spectator realizes that a particular cinematographic device has been employed in a film, and this in a way that is “fresh” or pleasantly innovative. Imagine, then, that this is a positively valenced property having “aesthetic” merit in the sense articulated above; imagine as well that it is also a fine-artistic merit because the viewer’s pleasure is based partly on an admiration of the filmmakers’ skillful employment of the medium. Let us suppose as well that the same cinematic work manifests many other particular attributes, such as moral and epistemic merits and demerits directly related to the manner in which the film’s historical subject matter is depicted. For example, the various complex elements of the film’s production design achieve a high level of historical verisimilitude, as is fitting to the genre and story. Even spectators having considerable expertise regarding the historical context in question find these aspects of the film remarkable and praiseworthy. Yet, suppose as well that these same spectators rightly find other features of the work highly criticizable. Important aspects of the characterizations lack verisimilitude. Moreover, other features of the story and characterization are objectionable because they were patently designed to elicit admiration for what our spectators identify as reprehensible behavior and attitudes. As a result of these divergent qualities and the conflicting responses they occasion, the tension between positively valenced aesthetic merits and negatively valenced moral and epistemic flaws becomes central to the appreciator’s experience of the film. The properties and relations in the work that ground this tension may be counted as an aesthetic and fine-artistic shortcoming, on the assumption that coherence, or unity in diversity, is a relevant desideratum.

      In such a case, in assessing the film, competent appreciators may be capable of distinguishing clearly between many of the determinate valenced qualities they have experienced in attending to the work: such-and-such qualities were aesthetically pleasing and artistically meritorious; such-and-such qualities had epistemic or pedagogical value; others still were ethically dubious or objectionable. There is, however, no way to arrive at a simple summation of these disparate valences. One cannot, for example, assign a score of -x units of value to the film’s dubious moral content and a score of + y units of value to its aesthetic qualities, and so on, so that when added up, these units of value would jointly be indicative of the overall merit of the work as a whole. And yet a report and verdict regarding the work’s overall merit is what the appreciator is often expected to provide. One is asked for an overall recommendation (or condemnation) of the film; in some institutional contexts, the work is to be ranked in relation to other works and awarded or denied some prize or other distinction.

      Note

      1 1 I thank Mette Hjort and Ted Nannicelli for the invitation to take up this topic for the purposes of their collection, and for helpful editorial comments on a draft of the chapter.

      References

      1 Angier, Tom. 2010. Technē in Aristotle’s Ethics: Crafting the Moral Life. London: Continuum.

      2 Aristotle. 1984a. “Nicomachean Ethics.” In The Complete Works of Aristotle, translated by W. D. Ross and edited by Jonathan Barnes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

      3 _____. 1984b. “Metaphysics.” In The Complete Works of Aristotle, translated by W. D. Ross and edited by Jonathan Barnes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

      4 _____. 2004. Nicomachean Ethics, translated and edited by Roger Crisp. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

      5 Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1983. Texte zur Grundlegung der Aesthetik, translated and edited by Hans Rudolf Schweizer. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

      6 Bolzano, Bernard. 1849. Über die Eintheilung der schönen Künste. Eine ästhetische Abhandlung. Prague: Gottlib Haase.

      7 Bordwell, David. 2019. “The Spectacle of Skill: BUSTER SCRUGGS as Master Class.” Observations on Film Art (blog), David Bordwell’s website on cinema. January 13, 2019. http://www.davidbordwell.net/blog/2019/01/13/the-spectacle-of-skill-buster-scruggs-as-master-class.

      8 Canudo, Ricciotto. 1911. “La naissance d’un sixième art: Essai sur le cinématographe.” Les entretiens idéalistes 10 (6): 169–79.

      9 Dio Chrysostom. 1951. Discourses, translated by Henry Lamar Crosby. London: William Heinemann.

      10 Du Bos, l’Abbé Jean-Baptiste. 1733. Réflexions critiques sur la poësie et sur la peinture, 2nd ed. rev., 3 vols. Paris: Pierre-Jean Mariette.

      11 Feagin, Susan. 1994. “Valuing the Artworld.” In Institutions of Art: Reconsiderations of George Dickie’s Philosophy, edited by Robert J. Yanal, 51–72. University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

      12 Goodhart-Rendel, Harry Stuart. 1934. Fine Art. Oxford: Clarendon.

      13 Harris, James. 1744. Three Treatises. London: H. Woodfall.

      14 Heathwood, Chris. 2015. “Monism and Pluralism about Value.” In The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory, edited by Iwao Hirose and Jonas Olson, 136–57. New York: Oxford University Press.

      15 Iseminger, Gary. 2004. The Aesthetic Function of Art. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

      16 Korsmeyer, Carolyn. 2001. Savoring Disgust: The Foul and the Fair in Aesthetics. New York: Oxford University Press.

      17 Lewis, Clarence Irving. 1946. An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

      18 Livingston, Paisley. 2004. “C. I. Lewis and the Outlines of Aesthetic Experience.” The British Journal of Aesthetics 44 (4): 378–92. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjaesthetics/44.4.378.

      19 _____. 2006. “Utile et dulce: A Reply to Noël Carroll.” The British Journal of Aesthetics 46 (3): 274–81. https://doi.org/10.1093/aesthj/ayl005.

      20 Pliny the Elder. 1951. Natural History, translated and edited by Howard Rackham. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

      21 Rind, Miles. 2002. “The Concept of Disinterestedness in Eighteenth-Century Aesthetics.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 40 (1): 67–87. https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2002.0017.

      22 Sextus