nothing; Am, An, Bm, Bn, any members of the two series of terms, and ΣA, ΣB, Σ(A,B) logical sums of some of the An’s, the Bn’s, and the (An,Bn)’s respectively.)
From these definitions a series of theorems follow syllogistically, the proofs of most of which are omitted on account of their ease and want of interest.
Theorems
I
If
II
If
III
If
IV
If
Corollary.—These last two theorems hold good also for arithmetical addition.
V
If
This theorem does not hold with logical addition. But from definition 6 it follows that
No a is b (supposing there is any a)
No a’ is b (supposing there is any a’)
neither of which propositions would be implied in the corresponding formulæ of logical addition. Now from definitions 2 and 6,
Any a is c
∴ Any a is c not b
But again from definitions 2 and 6 we have
Any c not b is a′ (if there is any not b)
∴ Any a is a′ (if there is any not b)
And in a similar way it could be shown that any a’ is a (under the same supposition). Hence by definition 1,
Scholium.—In arithmetic this proposition is limited by the supposition that b is finite. The supposition here though similar to that is not quite the same.
VI
If
VII
If
VIII
If
IX
If
The proof of this theorem may be given as an example of the proofs of the rest.
It is required then (by definition 3) to prove three propositions, viz.
1st. That any u is x.
2d. That any v is x.
3d. That any x not u is v.
First Proposition
Since
Any u is m,
and since
Any m is b,
whence Any u is b,
But since
Any u is a,
whence Any u is both a and b,
But since
Whatever is both a and b is x
whence Any u is x.
Second Proposition
This is proved like the first.
Third Proposition
Since
Whatever is both a and m is u.
or Whatever is not u is not both a and m.
or Whatever is not u is either not a or not m.
or Whatever is not u and is a is not m.
But since
Any x is a,
whence Any x not u is not u and is a,
whence Any x not u is not m.