Craig Smith

Adam Smith


Скачать книгу

can hope to achieve, but this is not a counsel of despair. Instead, for him, it is a call to modesty, a realization that beyond generalization from evidence we have no reliable source of knowledge. Hume thought that metaphysics was a waste of time. All we can do is refine generalizations from experience and come to increasingly accurate descriptions of the general forces that drive the natural world. The human mind is an increasingly sophisticated system of generalization from experience, and the scientific method is merely the deliberate formulation of this process into a method of inquiry. Once we realize this, we recognize that the experimental approach, the generation of evidence from observation, is the only reliable guide to the uniform operation of nature. Hume summed up his position by noting that: ‘A true sceptic will be diffident of his philosophical doubts, as well as of his philosophical convictions; and will never refuse any innocent satisfaction, which offers itself, on account of them.’5

      The power of Hume’s philosophical exploration of the basis of human knowledge made a deep impression on Adam Smith. Nicholas Phillipson has described Smith as the ‘perfect Humean’,6 and while this may be taking things too far, it is nonetheless clear that Hume deeply influenced his thinking on the nature of philosophy and science, the topic of the next chapter.

      Adam Smith is most famous as the author of the Wealth of Nations, but as the current volume aims to show by introducing the reader to his complete body of thought, this sits within a wider systematic body of work. In this chapter we will examine the outline of Smith’s system and then proceed to look at his views on science and system. This will set the scene for the following chapters, where we will look in some detail at his moral, political, and economic writings.

      In addition to these two books, we have the posthumous collection of unfinished essays, the Essays on Philosophical Subjects, published in 1795. We will cover the more important of these essays in the section below on science, but the volume also included some reflections on the role of imitation in the arts, an essay on poetry, and another on sense perception. The modern edition of this collection, part of the Glasgow edition of Smith’s works, also includes a series of minor letters and reviews.

      In his correspondence, Smith mentions two other projected volumes: one on the history of the arts, literature, and sciences and another on justice and politics. Neither of these came to fruition. However, we have been fortunate enough to discover student notes covering his Glasgow University Lectures on Jurisprudence and Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres. These are reasonably complete and have allowed us to reconstruct both his teaching and the main themes that he sought to convey to his students. They also show that Smith was developing many of the ideas that would later appear in the Wealth of Nations while he was a Professor at Glasgow in the 1750s and 1760s.

      Smith develops this method because he is dissatisfied with how a lot of philosophy had been undertaken in the past. He is generally dismissive of the view that philosophy can helpfully be pursued in seclusion from everyday experience of the world. Excessive abstraction can lead philosophers to produce elegant theories and beautiful arguments that crumble as soon as they come into contact with experience of the real world. Smith is absolutely committed to providing evidence for his claims and to avoiding the danger that ‘wrong systems’ that are a ‘refinement of philosophy’2 can take root and mislead us. Smith, in line with the mainstream of the Scottish Enlightenment, demands that theorizing must be supported by actual data gained from observation of life as it is, or as it has been lived.

      To start to understand Smith’s methodology and the version of the science of man that he developed in response to his reading of Newton and Hume, we should turn to his final, posthumous, publication, the Essays on Philosophical Subjects. The Essays were published in 1795, five years after Smith’s death, and represent the only unpublished papers that he thought worth saving. The rest of his papers were burned shortly before he died. His executors, the scientists Joseph Black and James Hutton, prepared the essays for publication and added a biographical essay by the Edinburgh philosopher Dugald Stewart. It may seem odd to look to Smith’s posthumous writing to start a consideration of his philosophical method, but this becomes less surprising if we understand that the most interesting essays in the volume were written early in Smith’s career and revised through his life. The three historical essays on Astronomy, Ancient Physics, and Ancient Logics and Metaphysics form part of Smith’s projected, but uncompleted, book on the history of art,