Julian Baggini

The Philosopher's Toolkit


Скачать книгу

in the sense that when you put in entirely good ingredients (all true premises), you get out a fine‐quality product (true conclusions). Of course, if you don’t start with good ingredients, deductive arguments don’t guarantee a good end product.

      Stranger still (and very different from sausage machines), with invalid deductive arguments you might sometimes put in poor ingredients (one or more false premises) but actually end up with a good result (a true conclusion). Of course, in other cases with invalid machines you put in poor ingredients and end up with rubbish. The thing about invalid machines is that you don’t know what you’ll get out. With valid machines, when you put in good ingredients (though only when you put in good ingredients), you have assurance. In sum:

       Invalid argument

       Put in false premise(s) → get out either a true or false conclusion

       Put in true premise(s) → get out either a true or false conclusion

       Valid argument

       Put in false premise(s) → get out either a true or false conclusion

       Put in true premise(s) → get out always and only a true conclusion

      Soundness

      To say an argument is valid, then, is not to say that its conclusion must be accepted as true. The conclusion is definitely established as true only if both of two conditions are met: (1) the argument is valid and (2) the premises are true. This combination of valid argument plus true premises (and therefore a true conclusion) is called approvingly a sound argument. Calling it sound is the highest endorsement one can give an argument. If you accept an argument as sound, you are really saying that one must accept its conclusion. The idea of soundness can even itself be formulated as an especially instructive valid, deductive argument:

      1 If the premises of the argument are true, then the conclusion must also be true (i.e. the argument is valid).

      2 The premises of the argument are true.

      3 Therefore, the conclusion of the argument must also be true.

      Importance of validity

      This may lead you to wonder why, then, the concept of validity has any importance. After all, valid arguments can be absurd in their content and false in their conclusions – as in our cheese and cats example. Surely it is soundness that matters?

      Okay, but keep in mind that validity is a required component of soundness, so there can be no sound arguments without valid ones. Working out whether or not the claims you make in your premises are true, while important, is also not enough to ensure that you draw true conclusions. People make this mistake all the time. They forget that one can begin with a set of entirely true beliefs but reason so poorly as to end up with entirely false conclusions. It can be crucial to remember that starting with truth doesn’t guarantee ending up with it.

      Furthermore, for the sake of launching criticisms, it is important to grasp that understanding validity gives you an additional tool for evaluating another’s position. In criticising a specimen of reasoning, you can either:

      1 attack the truth of the premises from which he or she reasons,

      2 or show that his or her argument is invalid, regardless of whether or not the premises deployed are true.

      Validity is, simply put, a crucial ingredient in arguing, criticising, and thinking well, even if not the only ingredient. It’s an utterly indispensable philosophical tool. Master it.

      SEE ALSO

      1 1.1 Arguments, premises, and conclusions

      2 1.2 Deduction

      3 1.5 Invalidity

      READING

       Aristotle (384–322 BCE). Prior Analytics

       Fred R. Berger (1977). Studying Deductive Logic

       S.K. Langer (2011). ‘Truth and validity'. In: Introduction to Symbolic Logic, 3rd edn, Ch. 1, pp. 182–90

       * Jc Beall and Shay Allen Logan (2017). Logic: The Basics, 2nd edn

      Given the definition of a valid argument, it may seem obvious what an invalid one looks like. Certainly, it’s simple enough to define an invalid argument: it is an argument where the truth of the premises does not guarantee the truth of the conclusion. To put it another way, if the premises of an invalid argument are true, the conclusion may still be false. Invalid arguments are unsuccessful deductions and therefore, in a sense, are not truly deductions at all.

      To be armed with an adequate definition of invalidity, however, may not be enough to enable you to make use of this tool. The man who went looking for a horse equipped only with the definition ‘solid‐hoofed, herbivorous, domesticated mammal used for draught work and riding’ (Collins English Dictionary) discovered as much, to his cost. In addition to the definition, you need to understand the definition’s full import. Consider this argument:

      1 Vegetarians do not eat pork sausages.

      2 Gandhi did not eat pork sausages.

      3 Therefore, Gandhi was a vegetarian.

      If you’re thinking carefully, you’ll have probably noticed that this is an invalid argument. But it wouldn’t be surprising if you and a fair number of readers required a double take to see that it is in fact invalid. Now, this is a clear case, and if a capable intellect can easily miss a clear case of invalidity in the midst of an article devoted to a careful explanation of the concept, imagine how easy it is not to spot invalid arguments more generally.

      So, the fact that Gandhi did not eat pork sausages does not, in conjunction with the first premise, guarantee that he was a vegetarian. It just so happens that he was. But, of course, since an argument can only be sound if it’s valid, the fact that all three of the propositions it asserts are true does not make it a sound argument.

      Remember that validity is a property of an argument’s structure of form. In this case, the form is:

      1 All Xs are Ys.

      2 Z is a Y.

      3 Therefore, Z is an X.

      Here