Tim Markham

Digital Life


Скачать книгу

thing to do over dinner, and yet it can be registered as both absurd and as grounding the ethics of co-existence. And the same can be said of our relations with digital technology: ultimately what matters is not how well we understand how it works and with what political and material consequences, but the practical, at-hand, embodied knowledge that this or that technology is both the way the world is disclosed to us, and at the same time a way. It remains important to work towards better public understanding of the way people’s consent is secured, their data monetized, their identities profiled, and with what economic, political and environmental implications. It is also important for us to understand what is revealed in the way people move balletically through digital spaces, seemingly accepting their proclivities and impositions as just the way things are now – this is how you get to know and to be. It turns out that their existential investment in such spaces is intuitive and yet restless enough to be open to other ways of being. There is a fundamental lack of absolute final commitment and resolution that both discloses the world as a world on the go, and makes known that it could, and will, be different in time.

      All of which brings us back to Couldry and Hepp and the laudable attention they give to the consequences for individuals’ everyday experience of the ‘world-making strategies of governing institutions’ (2017: 163). They take issue with Bruno Latour on the question of digital traces, and in particular Latour’s insistence that these give us direct access to experience. Instead, they counter that such directness cannot be assumed since those traces are dependent on the technical architectures and processes of institutions. Looked at another way, both perspectives are correct. It is undoubtedly right that we pay heed to the commercial and programmatic structuring of digital meaning-making practices, but if we take Heidegger’s account of thrownness seriously there is nothing less real about the meaningful experiences that emerge from such practices. Further, this generative inauthenticity does not commit Heidegger – or, I would argue, any of us – to accepting the status quo unquestioningly, nor does it absolve us of the responsibility for improving the (digital) world as we find it.

      This book takes its inspiration from Heidegger’s insight that the inauthentic world into which we are perpetually thrown, full of idle chat about everything and nothing as it is, is every bit as ontologically generative as any ‘deep’ apprehension of the human condition. Rather than the peripheral whispering of the void motivating the quest for meaning in everyday life, then, that locomotion is propelled by little more than affect-seeking and shallow curiosity. The performance of identity is similarly driven by the transient buzz of recognition, rather than realizing some final moment of subjectification. It can and has been argued that all of this meaningless digital stuff is a distraction from the human project of seeking enlightenment in relation to the questions of who we are and why we are here. The phenomenological endeavour, however, began by asking whether existential ethics would be best served by bracketing out such metaphysical concerns altogether. Thus, any serious consideration of what a digital ethics might look like should start from the ubiquitous distractions of our cluttered lives rather than seeking to take an abstracted position outside of this endless noise and light. Starting in media res, it soon becomes apparent that the low-level anxieties of digital life – not intimations of the abyss but generalized feelings of listlessness and dissatisfaction – are not problems to be tackled but that which keeps us in motion. And it is above all motion that comes to establish everything that a digital ethics should promote and protect – commonality, difference, complicity and responsibility in the here and now.

      Definitions and chapter overview