Gillian Brock

Migration and Political Theory


Скачать книгу

what means a government may use to enforce its immigration laws. For instance, may states separate children from their parents at the border if this is an effective way to get migrants to leave or not come in the first place? What criteria should we use in deciding what are the permissible and impermissible ways to enforce immigration policies?

      A second core set of questions involves our responses to unjust immigration policies or laws. We center the analysis around questions such as: Are sanctuary cities to be commended? Is it permissible to resist unjust immigration law? What forms of resistance, if any, might be justified in cases of unjust migration policy? Can people smuggling ever be permissible in response to unjust immigration policies?

      The chapter then proceeds to analyze how the emergence of the Covid-19 pandemic might affect political theorizing about migration in the future. The chapter concludes by briefly explaining why the recently adopted UN Global Compacts on migration might become important policy instruments that can help guide improved global migration governance in the future and why this would constitute significant progress.

      1 * Getting accurate data on migrants can be tricky because not all countries use the same definition of who counts as an international migrant. While a common account involves defining migrants as those who have changed their country of usual residence, some children who have never migrated are counted in these statistics.

      Those who argue in favor of more freedom of movement across borders often draw on two common lines of argument. One concerns massive injustice and inequality in the international sphere. Consider how people across the globe experience vast disparities in life prospects. Some states are incapable of providing even the most basic goods and services, such as clean water and safe sanitation, necessary for a decent life. Others seem to provide the essentials for a good life relatively reliably for almost all citizens. States vary greatly in the opportunities they can make available, including the opportunities for reasonably well-paid jobs, educational attainment, healthcare, and life expectancy. Those states that can offer such prospects are often thought to be desirable destinations and constitute considerable pull factors. And there are many relevant push factors as well that drive people to leave their countries of origin, searching for greener pastures. These include high levels of violence, dysfunctional or repressive governments, and civil war. So, because prospects for good lives are not evenly distributed across the world, this provides at least one dominant motivation for why some might seek to move.

      This brings us to a second common consideration in favor of opening borders, which concerns human freedom and the right to free movement. Among the important values that we often think states should respect are people’s freedoms, especially their freedom of movement. If states restrict entry to their territory, are they violating an important freedom? Would they be violating a human right that people should enjoy?

      Michael Walzer and Joseph Carens have been especially influential in debates on these issues of how open or closed our borders should be. They deserve a special focus, given that their arguments have largely set the terms for much contemporary debate, and as they offer opposing views, they will anchor the two central parts of this chapter.

       2.1.1 Walzer, self-determination and protecting the character of communities

      Walzer starts from the important idea that states are (or should be) self-determining communities and that