Группа авторов

Ethics at the Heart of Higher Education


Скачать книгу

been formed to some degree by practices of everyday life that have already required actions from them, actions that ended in moral failure or success. They most likely have also contemplated what was the proper course of action and thus engaged in theoretical reason. Both assume that the subject of ethics is human action either directed to the good (or right) and/or away from evil. “To do good and avoid evil,” wrote the thirteenth-century theologian Thomas Aquinas, is the first principle of the practical reason. This first principle should resonate with Southern Methodist University because the first two rules of the original Methodist societies, rules that remain in theory binding on all Methodists to this day, are first “do no harm, avoiding evil of every kind,” and second “do good.” (There is a third rule to attend upon the ordinances of God.) These first two rules restate the first principle of practical reason. It is, however, only a beginning point that assumes, on the whole, people in the course of their life try to do good and avoid evil. There may be persons who are sociopaths who seek evil and avoid good, but ordinary life would not be possible if they were the norm. Whether out of self-preservation or concern for others, most people do not drive willy-nilly through red lights. Why is this true? Is it because we seek to be (1) virtuous citizens, (2) faithful creatures before God, (3) moral agents who treat others as we desire to be treated, (4) individuals who maximize utility, or (5) agents who have been cared for by others and seek to extend that caring to others? Each of these options offers a theoretical response to the practical question of ethics. They describe how we go about being ethical and they prescribe how we should act. They also bring out five important moments in the history of ethics. One reason for the need to teach ethics is to know how those who came before us thought about ethics.

      (1) Aristotle’s Virtuous Citizen

      Perhaps we refuse to run through red lights because we have been trained in virtues that make us good citizens in our cities and neighborhoods. This would be the reason given by one of the earliest philosophers who taught ethics, the Greek philosopher Aristotle (384–322 BC). Although much has changed in the twenty-four hundred years since he lectured and wrote on ethics, his work is still widely used to help us understand what ethics is. Aristotle identified five “virtues of thought” that assist us in knowing what is true: craft (techne), scientific knowledge (episteme), practical wisdom (phronesis), wisdom (sophia), and understanding (nous). Craft is concerned with production similar to what builders, engineers and manufacturers make. The end product is external to the one who makes it so this kind of knowledge does not necessary produce virtue. For instance, one could be a morally compromised person and an excellent surgeon or car mechanic. It would be better if a surgeon were virtuous, but it is not necessary for her or his specific craft. Scientific knowledge is “demonstrative.” It discovers universals either through deduction or induction. Deduction begins with premises that are universally true and argues from them to conclusions that will also be universally true. Inductive reasoning begins with particular observations or probable premises and argues to conclusions that will be sound albeit not necessarily true. Understanding begins with principles that are undeniable; they are intrinsically known. Understanding provides the first principles for scientific knowledge. Wisdom is the ability to use understanding and scientific knowledge to arrive at conclusions that are “the same in every case.” Aristotle distinguished this from practical wisdom; its conclusions are actions that are not the same in every case. For instance, you should stop at red lights, but if you are driving your injured child to the hospital in the middle of the night, the light is red, and you clearly see there are no cars coming, practical wisdom would tell you to run the red light.

      For Aristotle, ethics is not a “speculative” discipline that provides necessary knowledge like mathematics, but a practical discipline whose knowledge can be other. That is to say, ethics cannot create a method, or a computer program, where we input an ethical dilemma and if everything works properly it concludes with a necessary result that would fit anyone in any context with any kind of education, formation or knowledge. Ethics is not a deductive science that is “demonstrative” and known universally. It is about “particulars,” contingent features of everyday life. How we see, define and act on those particulars will always be a matter of judgment made possible by our character. For this reason, practical wisdom is not productive in the same way that a craft is. It affects who the agent is more profoundly than a craft. Practical wisdom is the cultivation of virtue over time within a community that allows a moral agent to see well what is going on in a situation and, in turn, act virtuously. Ethics is as much about vision as it is about action because what we are unable to see excludes proper action. It is also about friendship and happiness or eudaimonia. The latter term translates as happiness or flourishing. For Aristotle, all action has a purpose, end or telos; it aims at a particular end—happiness. It alone contributes to human flourishing. Wealth, honor, status, health, or pleasure are not ends in themselves because even if we have them we want them for something other than themselves. They are means to some end, an end he identifies as eudaimonia.

      Aristotle’s ethics depends on the formation of character that requires “habituation.” It is the education resulting from practices that forms young boys into virtuous men. For Aristotle, ethical formation primarily occurred within the Athenian city by free males who had the leisure to pursue their flourishing. Ethics was not available to anyone, and for that reason contingency resided at the basis of ethics. Did a person have the right birth at the right time in the right place that would let him pursue those goods that made for human flourishing? Aristotle’s discrimination against women and slaves is no longer acceptable. His understanding of the ethics of virtue has, however, been translated into contemporary practices that remove these discriminations. Aristotle took as the paradigm for his ethics “the great souled man” who did not depend on anyone else while he himself had many who depended upon him. Few contemporary virtue theorists adopt the “great souled man” as a moral exemplar. Aristotle also argued that friendship was necessary for ethics; many contemporary virtue theorists adopt friendship as an essential aspect for virtuous living. Ethics is not accomplished by an isolated individual, but by a person with friends who assist him or her in the cultivation of virtue.

      (2) Thomas Aquinas’s Faithful Disciple

      Perhaps we do not run red lights because we seek to be faithful creatures before God, and doing harm to other creatures would at the same time be an offense to God in whose image they are made? However, despite our best efforts we find ourselves not doing the good we think we should do. We look for assistance, for something outside of us given by grace that causes us to do good works in the world. Thomas Aquinas (1225–74) was a Christian theologian and a member of the religious order known as the Order of Preachers who may have given this kind of answer. He accepted much of Aristotle’s teaching on ethics, but transformed it with theology. Like Aristotle, friendship was of central ethical importance, but Aquinas taught that the true end of the ethical life is found in friendship with God. For Aristotle, friends were primarily friends with others of a similar stature so the differences between God and humans ruled out the possibility that they could be friends. For Aquinas, friendship with God was not something that could be achieved on one’s own; it comes as a gift. Aristotle taught that virtues were acquired; they were habits that we achieve through proper habituation. Like many before him, he stated that the most important virtues were the “cardinal” virtues, from the Latin cardus, meaning “hinge”; they are the “hinge” that allows one to live well. Aquinas taught that friendship with God required something more than the acquired virtues; it required “infused” virtues that came from the Holy Spirit. They are “faith, hope and love,” and direct us to both God and our neighbor because to love God and neighbor fulfills the two tablets of the Ten Commandments given by God to Moses. To love God we must participate in God’s own love, and that participation makes possible infused virtues.

      (3) Immanuel Kant’s Autonomous Reasoner

      Although both Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas’s ethical teachings are still present in practice and theory today, they are not often the dominant ethical theories used in the modern university. They are considered too parochial. Modern ethical thinking originated with two seminal thinkers, Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) and J. S. Mill (1806–73). Perhaps we do not run red lights because if we lived by such a rule—I will willy-nilly run red lights—we could not will that everyone act by the same rule. Driving would be impossible.

      For