integral equal to the original function. Curiously, this “schooldays meaning”—integration as the reverse of differentiation—does not hold universally for the more widely used integration systems. See Section 10.2 of Chapter 10, which provides an overview of this subject.
The gauge integral (called ‐complete integral in [MTRV], and in this book) is non‐absolute. Other kinds of integration, such as Lebesgue's or Riemann's, have restrictive requirements of absolute convergence. But existence of ‐complete integrals requires only that the Riemann sum approximations converge non‐absolutely to the value of the integral; and this is central to the present book.
In [MTRV], instead of the more familiar term gauge integral, the term ‐complete integral (as in Riemann‐complete) is found to be helpful.2 This is because there are a great many different integration techniques—Riemann, Lebesgue, Stieltjes, Burkill, and others—which are used in different situations; most of which can be subsumed or adapted into a gauge integral system. But to assign indiscriminately the blanket designation “gauge integral” to each of the adapted versions is to ignore, firstly, their considerable difference in usages and origins; and, secondly, the fact that “gauge integral” has become practically a synonym for the one‐dimensional generalized Riemann (or Riemann‐complete) integral—also known as the Kurzweil‐Henstock integral.
Also, the general or abstract integral—called Henstock integral in chapter 4 of [MTRV]—has diverged historically from the more mainstream gauge or Kurzweil integration which has “integral‐as‐antiderivative” as its driving force. This aspect of the subject is touched on in Chapter 10 below.
The integral‐as‐antiderivative feature of one‐dimensional Riemann‐complete integration was mentioned in passing in Henstock's 1962–63 exposition [70], which concentrated on other aspects of integration (such as limit theorems3 and Fubini's theorem).
As a student Henstock was attracted to the theory of divergent series. When in 1944 he applied to Paul Dienes to do research in this subject, he was steered towards integration theory [11]; and his subsequent work often focussed on the margins between divergence and convergence.4
The gauge idea made its first appearance in Henstock's published work in [69], in a scenario of extreme divergence in which the gauge method is “tested to destruction” in its first public outing. (This counter‐example is rehearsed in pages 178–181 of [MTRV], section 4.14, Non‐Integrable Functions. See also Example 13 below.) There is no mention in his 1955 paper [69] of the reversal of differentiation which many students of the subject have found so useful. Nor does it touch on the notion of random variation in which theories of integration and measure play a central role, and where integral convergence is much more important than differentiation.5
The emphasis on convergence is maintained in the present book, which can be read as a stand‐alone, self‐contained, or self‐explanatory volume expanding on certain themes in [MTRV]. Like [MTRV] this book aspires to simplicity and transparency. No prior knowledge of the subject matter is assumed, and simple numerical examples set the scene. There is a degree of repetitiveness which may be tedious for experts. But experts can cope with that; more consideration is owed to less experienced readers.
For reasons demonstrated in [MTRV], and amply confirmed in the present volume, non‐absolute convergence is one of the characteristics which, in comparison with other methods, makes the gauge (or ‐complete) integrals suitable for the two main themes of this book: stochastic calculus and Feynman integration.
Stochastic calculus is the branch of the theory of stochastic processes which deals with stochastic integrals, also known as stochastic differential equations. A landmark result is Itô’s lemma, or Itô’s formula.
Stochastic integration is part of the mathematical theory of probability or random variation. Broadly speaking, quantities or variables are random or non‐deterministic if they can assume various unpredictable values; and they are non‐random or deterministic if they can take only definite known values.
Classically, stochastic integrals are constructed by means of a procedure involving weak limits. The purpose of this book is two‐fold:
To treat stochastic integrals as actual integrals; so that the limit process which defines a stochastic integral is essentially the same as the limit of Riemann sums which defines the more familiar kinds of integral.
To provide an alternative theory of stochastic sums which achieves the same purposes as stochastic integrals, but in a simpler way.
Mathematically, integration is more complicated and more sophisticated than summation (or addition) of a finite number of terms. It is demonstrated that stochastic sums can achieve the same (or better) results as stochastic integrals do. In the theory of stochastic processes, stochastic sums can replace stochastic integrals.
Examples of concrete nature are used to illustrate aspects of stochastic integration and stochastic summation, starting with relatively elementary ideas about finite numbers of things or events, in which there is no difference between summation and integration. A basic calculation of financial mathematics (growth of portfolio value) is used as a reference concept, as a vehicle, and as an aid to intuition and motivation.
In a review [145] of a book [31], Laurent Schwartz stated:
Each of us [Schwartz and Emery] tried to help the probabilists absorb stochastic infinitesimal calculus of the second order “without tears”; I don't know whether any of us succeeded or will succeed.
This book is a further effort in this direction.
The action functionals of quantum mechanics (see (8.7), page below) are analogous to stochastic integrals. They appear as integrands in the infinite‐dimensional integrals used by R.P. Feynman in his theory of quantum mechanics and quantum electrodynamics.
In comparison with alternative approaches such as those of J. Schwinger ([147–150]) and S. Tomonaga ([88–92, 164, 165]), Feynman's method is said to be physically intuitive. It contrasts with the mathematics‐leaning approach of Paul Dirac [27]:
The present lectures, like those of Eddington, are concerned with unifying relativity and quantum theory, but they approach the question from a different point of view. Eddington's method is first to get the physical ideas clear and then gradually to build up a mathematical scheme. The present method is just the opposite—first to set up a mathematical scheme and then try to get its physical interpretation.
In reading [FH] it can be helpful to bear in mind that “[Feynman was] the outstanding intuitionist of our age …”, (attributed to Schwinger in [32]).
Feynman's first published paper on path integrals was [F1], Space‐time approach to non‐relativistic quantum mechanics [39]. In a long tradition of the relationship between physics and mathematics it entailed problems of a pure mathematical kind:
There are very interesting problems involved in the attempt to avoid the subdivision and limiting processes [in Feynman's construction of path integrals]. Some sort of complex measure is being associated with the space of functions
. Finite results can be obtained under unexpected circumstances because the measure is not positive everywhere, but the contributions from most of the paths largely cancel out. These curious mathematical problems are largely side‐stepped by the subdivision process. However, one feels as Cavalieri must have felt calculating the volume of a pyramid