Группа авторов

The Explosion of Life Forms


Скачать книгу

1992, p. 5). Even more accurate stipulations regarding molecular information storage have been made earlier by Nikolai Koltsov (Soyfer 2001, p. 726). As Watson and Crick did not notice Koltsov, it was Schrödinger’s speculations which made Crick think “that great things were just around the corner” (Crick 1990, p. 18), and as is well-known, Crick’s efforts have been crowned by the discovery of the double-helix structure of the DNA. So, something like Schrödinger’s aperiodic crystal did exist. Today, “reproducible hereditary information coded in nucleic acid molecules” (Sagan 2010, p. 304) is seen as a key ingredient of life, but still, there are exceptions even to this characterization. What about viruses without a DNA of their own? (On this question see Morange 2017, 103f).

      A (4) genetic definition of life would be “a system capable of Darwinian evolution by natural selection”; it takes into account the progressive development of life forms. Even without the assumption of an increasing complexity throughout evolutionary history, the evolutionary scenario is appealing. How so? It simply seems to make sense: in the moment self-replicating units emerged on Earth, those units filled their respective environment. Any replication carries with it the possibility for duplication errors, which leads (besides a lot of “waste”) to mutant versions of the original unit. Those mutants replicating more efficiently replicated more quickly. Limited resources provided, this leads to the dominance of particular replicators over others in a given environment, while some mutants were able to make use of new environments. As a result, Earth is soaked through with life, even in extreme environments totally hostile to human life, microbes (called extremophiles) exist.

      So, what is life? Popular today is a version of the genetic or Darwinian definition, characterizing life as a “self-sustained chemical system capable of undergoing Darwinian evolution“ (Joyce et al. 1994, xi), including the processes of “self-reproduction, material continuity over a historical lineage, genetic variation, and natural selection” (Cleland and Chyba 2010, p. 328). This definition excludes any potential life based on other components than chemistry-based Earth life. This is why the quest to define life has been revived not only in the context of synthetic biology but also in that of astrobiology. The definition also excludes viruses, as they are not self-sustained but need a host to replicate.

      Much about science is about the fuzziness and continuous transition in nature apart from human taxonomies. Maybe “life” is a categorial description, which is hard to apply to aspects of nature which nevertheless play an important role in the emergence of the phenomenon. When “the origin and the evolution of life coincide” (Maurel 2017, p. 22) and life is physics and chemistry with a history, the small size and gradualness of historical transitions may explain the difficulty to “capture” the moment when life on Earth emerged. “If the origin of life is seen as the evolutionary transition between the non-living and the living, then it is also necessary to recognize it as a historical process shaped in part by the vagaries of contingent events. It also suggests that attempts to draw a strict line between these two worlds may be meaningless. In other words, the appearance of life on Earth should be seen as a non-progressive evolutionary continuum that seamlessly joins the prebiotic synthesis and accumulation of organic molecules in the primitive environment, with the emergence of self-sustaining, replicative chemical systems capable of undergoing Darwinian evolution (Lazcano 2017b, p. 90).

      There still might have been accelerated transitions like later in the history of life (Eldredge and Gould 1972). We should avoid, however, demanding the emergence of life to be somewhat discontinuous in case we are only motivated by the desire to ascribe meaning and distinctiveness to our own status as living beings; we could be biased. Yet even if there is nothing special about organisms, this “does not mean an absence of significant differences deserving more thorough study by scientists” (Morange 2017, p. 107).

      A definition of life by a set of properties is the best we currently have. We used the example of water, to make clear that this may present a preliminary status only to describe life. Maybe we have to extend our informational perspective on life beyond genetic informationalism to understand the full phenomenon. This challenge may be more complex than initially imagined. Consider this: H2O may be water, but not that what we mean when we ask for water. Pure H2O – distilled water – would actually kill us; there is a lot more in the actual mix of “water” which makes it usable for us. Likewise, even if we identify the special relation of components which distinguishes living phenomena even