Группа авторов

Genetic Disorders and the Fetus


Скачать книгу

in counseling, training, and skill, he emphasized that nondirectiveness is an “active strategy” aimed at “evoking the client's competence and ability for self‐direction.” The expansion of genetic counseling training and degree programs has ameliorated many of these issues.

      Michie et al.270 studied nondirectiveness in genetic counseling. They defined directiveness as advice and expressed views about or selective reinforcement of counselees' behavior, thoughts, or emotions. As expected, they concluded that genetic counseling as currently practiced was not characterized, either by counselors, counselees, or a standardized rating scale they used, as uniformly nondirective.

      Clarke271 remarkably argued that nondirective genetic counseling in the context of prenatal diagnosis is “inevitably a sham,” largely because of the “structure of the encounter between counselor and client.” He further contended “that an offer of prenatal diagnosis implies a recommendation to accept that offer, which in turn entails a tacit recommendation to terminate a pregnancy” if the fetus is abnormal. In 1970272 it was emphasized that the offer of prenatal diagnosis was not associated with any explicit or implicit commitment to abort. Clarke271 further opined that “nondirective counseling was unattainable, despite the counselor's motives, since the offer and acceptance of genetic counseling has already set up a likely chain of events in everyone's mind.” Experienced clinical geneticists were taken aback by his views,273275 and rightly so. He regarded reproductive choice as part of the “1980s consumerism model of clinical genetics.”276 The personal values of geneticists/counselors may influence behavior in clinical practice and individual vigilance is necessary to abide by the nondirective principle. This may be less challenging than imagined given the reported highly valued benevolence, self‐direction, and pattern of concern for the welfare of others.276 Clarke ignored a fundamental tenet of genetic counseling founded in a free society, where choice is not a fad but a right. His ideas suggest contempt for the views (and hence choices) of the public, maintaining that respect for the handicapped is not achievable in a society that “makes judgments about what types of people are worthy of life.”276 Others have reported that people's decision‐making processes are more rational than they might appear to be.277 Simms278 noted that, with hindsight, 80 percent of parents with handicapped children would have aborted their pregnancies. Later, in taking Clarke to task, she concluded that it was “his professional duty to advise parents to the best of his ability, not to make decisions for them. They will have to live with the consequences: he will not.”279

      The intrinsic danger of using a directive approach is the opportunity (even subconscious or inadvertent) for the physician/counselor to insinuate his or her own religious, racial, eugenic, or other beliefs or dictates of conscience into the counseling that is offered.280 A breach of this principle, supported by some,281 invites the provider to visit upon the patient unwarranted conscious or subliminal prejudices. Some obstetricians, for example, are known to have specifically not offered or referred patients for prenatal genetic studies because of their antiabortion views and have unconscionably exaggerated the specific risks of amniocentesis in order to discourage prenatal genetic studies. A Mexican study showed that physicians in specialties other than clinical genetics tend to counsel directively.282

      In rare instances, family circumstances may challenge the need to adhere to personal autonomy and nondirective counseling. The right of one monozygous twin at 50 percent risk for Huntington disease not to know information after predictive testing should be respected. If there is possible harm to the co‐twin, Chapman suggested that testing should “be denied in the absence of mutual consent.”288 She further argued that in the interest of beneficence, directive counseling is acceptable for individuals at 50 percent risk of Huntington disease who suffer from depression, lack social support, and have a history of attempted suicide. For these patients, psychiatric evaluation and counseling, rather than predictive testing, have been recommended. In a 15‐year experience offering predictive counseling for Huntington disease, the Canadian authors emphasized the importance of preparation for receiving test results.289 In a study of counseling following prenatal diagnosis of Klinefelter syndrome, Marteau et al.290 found that pregnancy was almost two‐and‐a‐half times more likely to continue when counseling was provided by a geneticist.

      Ever‐increasing genetic testing using microarrays and whole‐exome sequencing introduced the counseling challenge following determination of secondary findings. This issue of possible genomic uncertainty should be addressed prior to any sample being obtained. The American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics (ACMG) have a list of 59 actionable disorders which geneticists are directed to communicate because of potential health and life‐saving opportunities (see Chapter 14). Patients may opt out of this potential directive counseling, and clearly have the right not to know.291 More difficult, however, are discoveries of variants of uncertain or unknown significance (VOUS) (see Chapter 14). Recognition, for example, in a newborn with epileptic encephalopathy, macrosomia, hypotonia, hypoglycemia, and dysmorphic facies of unknown compound heterozygous, instead of known homozygous mutations292 in the HERC1 gene, would pose a serious challenge to remain nondirective regarding future recurrence risks and options. Further complicating nondirectiveness is the realization that pathogenic variants may occur in disease‐free individuals.293

      Fortunately, it is very uncommon to have two parents with totally opposing views regarding the option of an abortion of an affected fetus. A counseling experience with a couple, both of whom were FBI agents, brought this issue into stark relief. The emotional exchange and the vested positions of the parties invited the “nondirective directive” to return home for their decision making while ensuring that they were in the possession of all necessary facts upon which rationality could trump.

      Incidental detection by ultrasound, for example, of a hypoplastic thymus,294 following a maternal‐age indicated amniocentesis of a 22q11.2 deletion provides another quandary when one parent with a few signs is found to harbor the same microdeletion. Certainty about the future phenotype would be unwise,295 with the discussion about pregnancy termination requiring definitive nondirectiveness.

      Concern for the individual

      Communication should not depend on questions posed by the patient, who may not be cognizant of the subject's dimensions or the available options. For example, in the