Andreas Reckwitz

Society of Singularities


Скачать книгу

forms of singularization from the past and the present.

      A specific example is the collection of various different objects under one identifiable brand, which is associated with the promise of uniqueness within the realm of cultural capitalism or with a particular aesthetic style.18 Entities of organic nature can also be singularized: house pets, gardens, or the desert and the Alps as particular places of biodiversity, for example.19 In every case, singularized things and objects are more than functional instruments; they either offer something in addition to that or they are exclusively cultural, affectively operating entities. As such, they are not stable throughout time but rather have their own object biographies. Generally, the elements and relations that constitute the inherent complexity and inner density of singular objects are highly diverse, and this is the case for obvious reasons. In this regard, materials, forms, and colors can play just as much a role as semantics, syntax, and the narrative, harmonic, melodic, or argumentative structures of texts, music, or theories.20

      As mentioned above, the fashioning of singular human subjects has traditionally been treated under the misleading rubric of individuality. Subjects are singularized when their uniqueness is socially recognized and valued and when they actively engage in and cultivate certain techniques that invite this recognition.21 In such cases, singularization means subjectification: the subject achieves an acknowledged degree of inherent complexity that defies typification (though this was and remains a possibility).22 Singularized subjects cannot be reduced to functional roles or hereditary groups. Magi, prophets, and rulers, to whom Max Weber ascribed the attribute of charisma, have traditionally been subjects who could claim to be inimitable.23 In modernity, artists and other creative people were the first to form milieus in which originality was both desired and demanded.24

      When spaces are singularized, they are elevated to what theorists of space have come to call places.27 The difference between space and place is the same as the difference between spaces in the social logic of the general and spaces in the social logic of singularization. Places are singular spaces in which material objects are arranged, endowed with meaning, and offered to be perceived in such a way that they are experienced as inherent complexities with specially composed spatial densities – as spaces unconfined by the standardization to which spaces are subjected in the social logic of the general. Such places are not simply used and passed through; rather, they seem valuable and emotionally attractive to those participating in them. Charming cities such as Venice and Paris – with their layouts and atmospheres, but also with the cultural associations and memories associated with them – are historical prototypes for “intrinsically logical” places.28 Yet places of worship, palaces, sacred buildings, exceptional landscapes, monuments, and even apartments and atmospherically rich office landscapes in the creative branches can also be special places in this sense. Whereas, in the logic of the general, all spaces are meant to fulfill a particular function in the same way, the logic of the particular turns spaces into places of identification. Here, to some extent, space is not extensive but rather intensive. Here it is the locality of the space that interests people. Only a space that has been condensed into a place can become a locus of memory and a setting with atmosphere.29

      In this case, time is not something that is habitually or routinely filled in order to achieve certain objectives beyond the present. For its participants, on the contrary, it has an intrinsic value of its own; it is experienced in the moment of its seemingly overwhelming complexity – in the presence of its presentness, so to speak.30 Whereas, in the mode of the general, temporality is desensitized to the present moment of activity and instrumentally oriented toward the future, in the mode of the particular it is present-oriented. However, such experiences might also involve references to the past: the memory of a previous event or the establishment of historical connections can serve to enrich the present. For this reason, historical narratives – which cultivate our “historical memory” of past events, moments, places, or people to the point of nostalgia – are likewise variations of temporality within the social logic of the particular.31

      Singular collectives are not general, instrumentally rational associations or (idiosyncratic) “given” social milieus; rather, they are collectives that have a unique cultural value for their participants. According to one theory of modernization, they might be referred to as “particular groups,” yet in this case the semantics of the particular is meant to devalue them as insignificant elements with limited scope as compared to the vast and general organizations of modern society. In reality, however, these collectives are more than just a part of something grander; from the perspective of their members, they are, rather, complete cultural universes of their own with high degrees of communicative, narrative, and affective complexity and significance. This was already true of any family genealogy with its own collective consciousness, but also of early-modern guilds and corporations whenever they were more than just instrumentally rational institutions. In (late) modernity, the singularization of collectives might also occur, for instance, in cultural and aesthetic subcultures, in self-chosen religious collectives, as well as in nations or regional communities (though in a somewhat different way).