Группа авторов

A Companion to Hobbes


Скачать книгу

and Ward as Six Lessons to the Professors of the Mathematiques as an appendix to the 1656 Of Body, the English translation of De corpore. The resulting controversy dragged on for the remainder of Hobbes’s life, and it is fair to say that all of his mathematical publications after 1655 are directed against Wallis and written in the shadow of his Elenchus. As he summed up the case in the Preface to Lux:

      A certain book of Hobbes’s, De corpore, published early in 1655, provided the occasion for this dispute. The book contains among other things certain geometrical principles differing from the principles accepted today, and also a demonstration (as he termed it) of the equality of a certain right line and the fourth part of the circumference of the circle. This confidence of Hobbes displeased many mathematicians, especially in the famous universities, some of whom had perhaps thought that all the most difficult problems in geometry had been reserved for only them to solve. And so, in order to overturn this demonstration and the whole geometry of Hobbes, John Wallis, public professor of geometry at the university of Oxford published a book entitled Elenchus Geometriae Hobbianae. Εκ τοῦδε ἄρχεται ὁ πόλεμος [From thence arises the war] And this perpetual geometric war has been waged between them without pause. For almost nothing is written by one which is not publicly opposed by the other.

      (OL V.93)

      There is little to be gained from a close examination of each disputant’s contributions. Indeed, Hobbes himself dismissed Wallis’s works as “puerile, unsophisticated, unlearned, and boorish,” adding “Nor do I judge the replies I have made to your works to be worthy to be read by posterity” (OL IV.522). We can, however, gain some insight into Hobbes’s approach to geometry by examining some details of his method.

      3.2.2 The Method of Motion and Hobbes’s Geometric Ambitions

      This result was first published in the Hydraulica of Marin Mersenne, which was part of his 1644 collection Cogitata Physico-Mathematica. Mersenne reported the discovery of the result: “when I was concerned with this result, a learned man proposed a certain straight line that he though equal to the first revolution of the spiral abcdefn, but the revolution of the spiral was greater than this proposed line, and our geometer showed that the spiral was equal to the parabola GT” (Mersenne 1644, 129). The “learned man” is Hobbes, and “our geometer” is Roberval. It is therefore clear that Hobbes was well acquainted with the method of motion in the 1640s through his contact with Roberval by way of Mersenne (Malcolm 2002).

      The method of motion dominates the geometrical sections of De corpore and it is the source of the putative results with which Hobbes hoped to assert his claim to pre-eminence in geometry. The catalog of these mathematical contributions includes an analysis of parabolic arcs in the style of Galileo (chapter XVI), the quadrature of parabolic segments that builds on Cavalieri’s approach (chapter XVII), a supposed rectification of parabolic arcs (chapter XVIII) and a putative quadrature of the circle (chapter XX). Throughout these chapters Hobbes examines the motions by which geometric magnitudes are generated or transformed – comparing the uniform motion of a point in one direction with its accelerated motion orthogonal to that motion, or examining the “flexion” by which a curved arc can be straightened and compared to a given line (Dunlop 2016; Jesseph 2017).

      3.3 Conclusion