P. M. S. Hacker

Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience


Скачать книгу

       (3) Incoherence in Eccles’s hypothesis

      Third, Eccles’s main hypothesis is unintelligible. If the self-conscious mind were, per impossibile, ‘actively engaged in reading out’ from areas in the dominant hemisphere and ‘selecting from these modules according to attention’, then the self-conscious mind would have to perceive or be aware of the neural modules in question (otherwise how could it ‘read them out’?), and know which ones to select for its purpose (otherwise the wrong ones might constantly be selected). Or, to put matters more lucidly, for any of this story to make sense, human beings would have to be aware of the neural structures and operations in question, and, from moment to moment, decide which ones directly to activate, and, of course, have the capacity to do so. But we possess no such knowledge and no such capacity.

      (4) The very notion of the self-conscious mind presupposes the unity of experience

      Finally, it is confused to suppose that the raison d’être of the ‘self-conscious mind’ is to engender the unity of the self and, as our contemporaries would put it, ‘solve the binding problem’. For any talk of a person or of a human being as having a mind already presupposes the unity of experience and cannot be invoked to explain it.

      Eccles’s errors cannot be rectified by substituting the brain for his conception of the ‘self-conscious mind’

      2.4 Wilder Penfield and the ‘Highest Brain Mechanism’

      Penfield’s training

      Wilder Penfield (1891–1976) was born in Spokane, Washington. After graduating from Princeton in 1913, he won a Rhodes Scholarship to Oxford and entered the School of Physiology there to begin his medical studies under the inspiring influence of Sherrington. He followed Sherrington’s interest in histology and, in particular, in neurocytology. After obtaining his BA in physiology at Oxford, he went to the Johns Hopkins Medical School, where he finished his medical degree in 1918. His first research concerned changes in the Golgi apparatus of neurons after axonal section. In 1924 he began to study the healing processes of surgical wounds in the brain. On Sherrington’s advice, he spent some time in Madrid working with Pio del Rio-Hortega, learning to use the histological methods of his brilliant teacher Ramón y Cajal. To this end, surgical specimens of brain scars were collected from patients who had been operated on for post-traumatic epilepsy.

      Penfield’s achievement

      Penfield was aware of the studies on cortical localization in the primate brain that Sherrington had carried out, and which have been described above. In 1928 he went to Breslau to work with Otfrid Foerster, to learn his method of gentle electrical stimulation of the cortex of epileptic patients while they were under local anaesthesia during the excision of epileptogenic scar tissue. During these procedures he learned the method of operating under local anaesthesia, using electrical stimulation to identify the sensory and motor cortex to guide the surgical excision. This technique was to be used to singular effect by Penfield in Montreal, where, in 1934, he established the famous Montreal Neurological Institute at McGill University, which was devoted to the study and surgical treatment of focal epilepsy. Such stimulation made it possible to locate exactly the position of the sensorimotor cortex and of the cortex subserving speech, so that these vital areas could be spared during the surgical excision. In some instances the stimulation might activate the more excitable epileptogenic cortex and reproduce a portion of the patient’s habitual seizure pattern. This enabled the surgeon to identify the site of the physiologically deranged epileptic focus. Penfield’s mastery of these procedures was subsequently summarized in a series of monographs on brain surgery for epilepsy.

      Penfield’s methodological commitment

      Penfield on the mind