P. M. S. Hacker

Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience


Скачать книгу

The conception is confused, since although we distinguish material objects from mental states, and both from propositions or theorems, these do not collectively constitute ‘worlds’ in any sense whatsoever. Furthermore, neither mental states nor propositions are denizens of a distinct ‘world’. There is only one world, which is described by specifying whatever is (contingently) the case. We do indeed talk of people’s mental states of cheerfulness or depression, or of their having toothache. But this does not imply that cheerfulness, depression or toothache are peculiar mental entities that exist in an ‘inner world’. These nominals (‘cheerfulness’, ‘depression’, ‘toothache’) merely provide an indirect way of talking of people being cheerful or depressed and of their tooth’s hurting – it introduces no new entities, merely new ways of talking about existing entities (e.g. about human beings and how things are with them). Similarly, we talk of propositions, theorems and other abstracta – but this too only appears to introduce new entities, and is really no more than a convenient way of talking about what is or might be said, asserted, or proved, etc. There is absolutely no need to succumb to Platonism and conjure new entities into existence and new worlds for them to inhabit. All talk of expressions standing for ‘abstract entities’ is a misleading way of saying that expressions that look as if they stand for concrete entities do not do so at all, but rather fulfil quite different functions. To be sure, this does not mean that there are no mental states, no cheerfulness, depression or anxiety, or that there are no propositions, no theories or theorems. On the contrary, it means that there are – only they are not kinds of entities.

      The impact on Eccles of Kornhuber’s research on readiness potential

      Research done by Kornhuber and his colleagues (see §1.6.1) on changes in electrical potential antecedent to a voluntary movement had revealed that the so-called readiness potential began up to 800 milliseconds before the onset of the muscle action potential, and led to a sharper potential, the pre-motion positivity, beginning at 80–90 milliseconds prior to the movement. The patterns of neuronal discharges eventually project to the appropriate pyramidal cells of the motor cortex and synaptically excite them to discharge, so generating the motor potential (a localized negative wave) just preceding the motor pyramidal cell discharge that initiates the movement. The question on which Kornhuber’s research seemed to throw light was: ‘How can willing of a muscular movement set in train neuronal events that lead to the discharge of pyramidal cells of the motor cortex and so to the activation of the neuronal pathways that lead to the muscle contraction?’ (HM 214). It is striking that Eccles took these discoveries to betoken empirical confirmation of mind–brain interaction of a kind (but in a different location) that had been envisaged by Descartes. He argued as follows:

      What is happening in my brain at a time when the willed action is in the process of being carried out? It can be presumed that during the readiness potential there is a developing specificity of the patterned impulse discharges in neurons so that eventually there are activated the pyramidal cells in the correct motor cortical areas for bringing about the required movement. The readiness potential can be regarded as the neuronal counterpart of the voluntary intention. The surprising feature of the readiness potential is its very wide extent and gradual build up. Apparently, at the stage of willing a movement, there is a very wide influence of the self-conscious mind on the pattern of module operation. Eventually this immense neuronal activity is moulded and directed so that it concentrates onto the pyramidal cells in the proper zones of the motor cortex for carrying out the required movement. The duration of the readiness potential indicates that the sequential activity of the large numbers of modules is involved in the long incubation time required for the self-conscious mind to evoke discharges from the motor pyramidal cells … It is a sign that the action of the self-conscious mind on the brain is not of demanding strength. We may regard it as being more tentative and subtle, and as requiring time to build up patterns of activity that may be modified as they develop.(HM 217)

      Cartesian problems recapitulated:

       (1) Interaction

      So, Eccles conceived of what he called ‘the dualist-interactionist hypothesis’ as helping to ‘resolve and redefine the problem of accounting for the long duration of the readiness potential that precedes a voluntary action’ (HM 217). Descartes, as we have noted, conceived of the mind as operating upon the pineal gland to generate the minute fluctuations in the animal spirits (the role-equivalent of neural transmitters) in the ventricle in which he thought the pineal gland was suspended. This, he held, enabled the acts of will of the mind to affect the motions of the animal spirits, which are then transmitted to the muscles. But the question of how an immaterial substance could actually interact causally with a material object such as the pineal gland to produce the appropriate minute motions was left totally unanswered. In much the same way, Eccles thought that the ‘self-conscious mind’ interacts causally with the pyramidal cells of the motor cortex, gradually (rather than instantaneously) getting them to discharge. But the question of how an immaterial entity such as the mind can interact causally with neurons was left equally unanswered.

       (2) Reifying the mind

       (3) Misconceptions about the will

      Eccles was further confused over the object of the alleged act of will, which is variously characterized as (i) a muscular movement, (ii) an action or (iii) a movement of a limb.

      Confusions about the object of the alleged act of will

      It is, of course, possible to intend to move a muscle – for example, to flex a muscle – but that is something we rather rarely intend to do, and although the movement of muscles is involved in all our positive, physical acts ( by contrast with acts of omission and mental acts), what we intend, and what we voluntarily perform, are actions (such as raising our arm, writing a letter, saying something, picking up a book, reading a book, and so on), and not the constitutive muscle movements of these actions, of which we are largely unaware. But it is easy to see why a neuroscientist who is attracted to dualism should confuse the objects of the will. For, according to the dualist conception, the mind has causally to affect the brain, and the causal powers of neural events in the brain causally affect muscle contraction.

      Problems of volitional interaction between mind and brain

      This raises yet a further insoluble problem for the dualist. The ‘self-conscious mind’ is supposed to influence the pattern of module operation, gradually moulding and directing it so that it concentrates on the pyramidal cells in the proper zones of the motor cortex for carrying out the intended movement. But how does the ‘self-conscious mind’ know which pyramidal cells to concentrate on, and how does it select the proper zones of the motor cortex? For it would need such knowledge in order to execute such actions. And it is certainly