Группа авторов

A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value


Скачать книгу

things are valuable because we value them. Now, what initially motivates Socrates’s question is the desire to know what piousness is, and his question assumes that such knowledge is essentially a matter of being able to define and describe the nature of piousness. So, it may seem we face a similar dilemma in attempting to say what value is. However, one might simply reject the assumption that knowledge of what value is and the ability to describe value necessarily requires one to provide a definition or an account of its nature. This is the point Peter Geach makes in his analysis of Euthyphro, in which he observes, “We know heaps of things without being able to define the terms in which we express our knowledge. Formal definitions are only one way of elucidating terms; a set of examples may in a given case be more useful than a formal definition (1966, 371). The upshot of this argument is that the best way of elucidating a slippery concept like value may simply be to point to and try to describe the way we use the term in language and conceive of the concept of value in our everyday practices.

      In fact, this is what many, if not all, of the contributors do tacitly throughout the book. The book’s seven-section structure, too, suggests something about value that may seem obvious, but that is far from trivial: the evidence from our practices suggests that value is plural—that there are distinct domains of value that may not be reducible to a single kind of value (or good). We seek out aesthetic experiences, spiritual experiences, social encounters, interaction with the natural environment, and so forth in ways that indicate those experiences afford a plurality of goods. So, too, we create, seek out, and watch motion pictures that offer those same experiences either directly or imaginatively and, thus, also afford the various sorts of goods outlined by the sections of this book.

      Nevertheless, it should be noted here that this take on value as essentially socially sustained raises one more difficult question that we should briefly address. As we pointed out in objecting to desire accounts of value, one challenge for explicating value is to accurately account for the fact that, in the sorts of practices described above, we speak and act as if people can be mistaken or misguided about value. In this sense, value is an essentially normative concept. It is worth saying a bit about what this means and does not mean in the present context.

      We may not necessarily agree on what an ideal vacation would be, but we have a shared understanding of the criteria for something to count as a vacation as well as the sorts of qualities that make a vacation good (relaxation, fun, a change of scenery, etc.) and those that make a vacation bad (stress, illness, logistical problems, lousy weather). In our social practice of vacationing, value is relativized to the kinds of things vacations are, but is nevertheless objective because the criteria for kind-membership and being good of a kind are intersubjectively shared. It is in this sense that value is an essentially normative concept in virtue of the way it is socially sustained. The example of vacations is our own, but it falls under a broader category of what Raz calls “genre- or of kind-constituting values;” for Raz, “a genre or a kind of value combines two features: it defines which objects belong to it, and in doing so it determines that the value of the object is to be assessed (inter alia) by its relations to the defining standards of the genre” (2008, 39). The defining standards of a genre or kind, while socially dependent and contingent, have an objective existence; they are intersubjectively available to members of a given society, sustained and taught in the relevant social practice.

      The points made by Carroll and Wolterstoff can be put together in a way that bears upon our discussion of the objectivity of value and the plurality of values afforded by social practices. Another way of putting Wolterstorff’s point about the diverse ways of engaging art is to say that art fulfills a variety of functions and offers us a variety of different goods. It is not implausible to think that particular artifact kinds, including art and motion pictures more specifically, might have multiple functions or purposes and afford multiple sorts of value (see, e.g., Stecker 1997). Wolterstorff (2015) persuasively argues that art can have the functions of memorializing, of venerating, of protesting, of pursuing justice. It can also have the purposes of persuading, educating, and strengthening community relationships. The list goes on, and the point applies, mutatis mutandis, to motion pictures.

      There is an important connection here between function and value: it is plausible to think of kinds that have primary or “proper” functions as good of their kind insofar as they fulfill that function (see Stecker 1997; Parsons and Carlson 2008). Furthermore, it is also plausible that whether a particular kind has a primary or “proper” function is an objective matter. This is perhaps obviously true of biological kinds—a good liver is one that rids the body of toxins and a bad liver is one that does not fulfill that function—but it is also true of many artifact kinds. Both Raz and Carroll discuss movies at length to make this point. One of Carroll’s examples is slapstick comedy: “given the point or purpose of [slapstick] comedy—its function, if you will—pratfalls contribute to the goodness of a slapstick comedy and the lack of them, all things being equal, would be detrimental” (2009, 164). There is a missing premise here, but it is fairly uncontroversial (and Carroll supplies it later on)—i.e., that the aim or purpose of slapstick comedy is “the provocation of laughter through physical business, often of an apparently accidental sort” (2009, 168). Whether all artifact kinds, let alone art, have such determinate purposes or proper functions is a matter of debate. Yet whether a particular kind has such functions is an objective matter (albeit a socially-established, contingent one), as is whether a candidate kind has the right sorts of features and fulfills the relevant function to be good of its kind. Clearly enough, some genres or kinds of motion pictures do, and this secures the objectivity of their value.