on the rise.
Others might argue that this is none of the state’s business, and that policies such as this are instances of the nanny state. This account would argue, perhaps, that politics is for defending rights, protecting property and liberty, and administering the state; what people want to drink, smoke or do in their own time is none of government’s business.
The City of New York’s proposal failed to be implemented, not because it was determined that it was an overreach of the City’s powers, but rather because it would only affect businesses licensed by the City, and many locations inside the city were licensed by the state and were not subject to City regulations on this issue. Equity was at stake here; certain businesses would have been free to sell sugary drinks by the bucket load, whilst others would have restrictions placed upon them, and this would have led to an unequal marketplace. Fairness in the application of principles was deemed a more important goal of politics than health.
Chapter overview
This chapter aims to begin our reflections on politics by examining what politics is about? What type of aims should we have from politics? How has politics been conceptualized? This chapter will commence in ancient Athens, then move from Renaissance Florence to nineteenth-century England, then hop over to Germany, before travelling across the Atlantic to the United States in the 1970s, before returning to Germany. As you might expect from such a journey, the ranges of responses to the question ‘what is politics about?’ are varied.
Our first discussion will be a brief examination of the life of Socrates and to see how he placed a search for justice at the heart of politics, and thought that we should all regard this quest as being central to our lives. Indeed, he became a martyr for this quest. We will then examine Machiavelli’s advice to politicians outlined in his work The Prince. We will see here that it is not morality that should be at the heart of politics, as it is pointless always being moral as a prince because if you do you will lose your position to someone who is not as good as you. This does not mean to say that the prince can do anything to keep his power though, as, for Machiavelli, glory is the purpose in politics, and glory places restraints on what a ruler can do.
We will then begin a comparison among utilitarian philosophers such as Bentham and Mill, who will argue that politics should be about bringing the greatest amount of happiness possible in politics. This will be contrasted with Kant, who argues that morality is the most important thing in politics. We will see that there exists between Kant and the utilitarian theorists a significant difference in how we formulate the nature of a moral act, with Kant focusing purely on the motivations behind an act, and the utilitarians examining the consequences of an act. Walzer will provide us with a potential halfway house between these competing perspectives on morality with his notion of dirty hands.
The chapter will conclude with an overview of Max Weber’s cautionary note against pure passion in politics, noting as he does that, with a centralized state with a monopoly of the use of legitimate force, this should be balanced with responsibility and a sense of purpose.
Socrates and the examined life
Socrates wrote nothing down, and the accounts we have on him are spartan, so it might seem strange to start a chapter on the nature of politics in a book on political theory with someone who leaves us with nothing to examine. It is rather his life that gives us a lesson in the nature of politics; he was a badass. He questioned whatever beliefs he wanted, cared not one iota for money or possessions, actively opposed the form of government in Athens at the time, and did not care who he upset in the process. The only Greek who comes close to beating him in the rock and roll stakes is Diogenes, who lived in a barrel and would walk around the marketplace in daylight with a lamp in the search for an honest man. Philosophy was not a subject to be abstractly studied in the classroom or the library for Socrates; it was to be lived. If one discovered a virtue, the notion that you should act differently to that virtue would have baffled him.
In The Apology, an account of the trial of Socrates, where he was being prosecuted on the charge of corrupting the youth of Athens, written by his devoted student Plato, Socrates outlines why it would be no good for them to exile him from Athens. Socrates was a controversial figure who questioned many of the religious and political beliefs that were dominant in the ancient Greek democracy. He philosophized on the street, gained adherents and enemies alike, and asked searching questions about the nature of virtue. He argued that if exiled he would just continue doing precisely that which he had done hitherto in another place:
Perhaps someone may say, ‘But surely, Socrates, after you have left us you can spend the rest of your life in quietly minding your own business.’ This is the hardest thing of all to make some of you understand. If I say that this would be disobedience to God, and that is why I cannot ‘mind my own business’, you will not believe me – you’ll think I’m pulling your leg. If on the other hand I tell you that to let no day pass without discussing goodness and all the other subjects about which you hear me talking and examining both myself and others is the very best thing that a man can do, and that life without this sort of examination is not worth living, you will be even less inclined to believe me. (Plato, 1993: 63, my emphasis)
Socrates is saying here that ‘discussing goodness’ is what we should all be doing every day, and, if we do not do this, we are wasting our lives. Those of us who get up, go to work, go home, watch TV, go to the pub, then go to sleep without thinking about, or better yet discussing with our peers, the nature of justice and politics, are not really living lives that are meaningful in any way. Discussing the kind of issues that are in this book is what makes life worth living. Consider this, when you attempt the activities throughout this book (especially if you do them with friends), you are not just testing your knowledge, or providing yourself with an aidemémoire, you are living a meaningful life for Socrates.
The unexamined life is not worth living for Socrates. We should, on a daily basis, question the nature of justice and morality, and we should live our lives according to our conclusions.
Socrates developed what has become known as the Socratic method as a way to examine concepts and beliefs; you can see this method at work in any of the Socratic dialogues written by Plato, and his use of him in The Republic. The Socratic method involved Socrates cross-examining his interlocutor, generally asking for a definition, then perhaps another example. If you are studying at college at the moment, you may have witnessed the Socratic method from your tutor without knowing it. Its purpose was to bring clarity of definitions and concepts in a search for truth, but often Socrates would try to show how the definitions and additional examples his colleague raised showed how their original assertion was false. As well as illuminating, they could sometimes destroy.
Socrates often tried to show how beliefs and contentions held by those he was talking to were in fact false. Nothing was worse for Socrates than claiming to know something which you did not know, or thinking you knew a lot when you did not. This is known as the Socratic irony, that the wisest people realize that they know nothing. Acceptance of the world of things which one does not know is a virtue for Socrates. He is not, however, defending ignorance here; far from it. What he is attacking is the pomposity and sophistry of those who claim to know more than they do. This is a political point, as he thought that in Athenian democracy, too much power was given to those who either knew nothing, or knew less than they claimed to know.
In response to this, Socrates developed the Craft Analogy. Politics should be seen as analogous to crafts. If your car broke down this morning, you would not take a vote amongst your friends about how to fix it; you would take it to a mechanic who is an expert in fixing cars. Likewise, if your mobile phone died, you would not necessarily canvass opinion from all and sundry as to how to fix it; you would take it to a specialist. So it is with the leadership of the state; it should be left to those with the most skill in that particular craft, people like Socrates, rather than being in the hands of everyone in a democracy. Plato would develop this point further in The Republic, but it is obviously undemocratic; not everyone has the skill to lead for Socrates,