Kris McDaniel

This Is Metaphysics


Скачать книгу

extent than other things. Think about this list of things: me, my wife, my two daughters, and my dog Ranger. Ranger is the odd man (odd dog?) out in this list. But now consider a larger list: me, my wife, my daughters, my dog Ranger, and the number 2. Despite being even, the number 2 is the odd number out. What this shows is that although Ranger doesn’t belong in the first group as much as my daughters do, he definitely belongs in the second group much more than the number 2. So, he must belong with me, my wife, and my daughters to some extent.

      1.11 What this means is that instead of focusing simply on the question of whether a specific classification is a good way of classifying, we should also consider the more general question of when a given classification is a better classification than another. We won’t have a complete theory of classification if we don’t consider this more general question.

      1.12 The second complication is that there are different reasons why we judge that things belong together, and these different reasons will sometimes lead to different and apparently conflicting ways of classifying objects. But these different ways of classifying objects don’t really conflict. We already saw an illustration of this phenomenon. Let’s return to one of the lists of things that we thought about at the beginning, specifically the one that consisted of a cat, a dog, a kangaroo, and a fish. There seemed to be two equally respectable ways of breaking this list into groups. We might separate the fish from the remaining three on the grounds that the remaining three are mammals; but we may also separate the kangaroo from the remaining three on the grounds that only the remaining ones are commonly taken as pets. Is there any point in trying to decide which of these two classifications is better? Isn’t how we classify things largely dependent on what we are interested in, what we care about, what we desire, and so forth?

      1.13 Sort of. There’s an important difference between the two kinds of classifications just mentioned. One of them classifies animals by looking to see whether they are related to us in some interesting social way: the classification that excludes kangaroos is based on the observations that we don’t interact with kangaroos in (some of) the ways in which we interact with dogs, cats, and fish. But it wasn’t inevitable that we don’t typically have kangaroos as pets. Imagine a possible situation in which we have kangaroos as pets instead of cats: if that possible situation had actually happened, then we probably would have felt that it was cats rather than kangaroos that do not belong on the list.

      1.15 One lesson to draw from these observations is that, roughly, there can be (at least) two kinds of systems of classification. We might classify objects because we are interested in how they relate to us. We can think of these as subjective classification systems because they are driven by our interests, desires, values, and so on. But a system of classification might also classify things on a more objective basis, that is, on grounds that are independent of whether that system of classification reflects anything about how reality relates to us or what we care about. Some things objectively belong together. An objective classification system is one that classifies things together in a way that matches how they objectively belong together.

      1.18 Social scientists—psychologists, sociologists, anthropologists, and so on.—would be good people to consult if we wanted to know why people lump things together for subjective reasons. Maybe biology, zoology, animal psychology, and other sciences like them, might also play a role in helping us figure this out. And it will sometimes be a tough job. Occasionally the explanation for why a group of people ended up classifying some objects as belonging together can be so subtle that the people doing the classifying aren’t even aware of these reasons. And when this happens, sometimes people falsely believe that the things that they have subjectively lumped together really objectively belong together. As we will see in a moment, at times this can also affect how people classify each other.

      1.20 If this is correct, then racial classifications are very subjective in the sense described earlier: racial classifications are based on contingent features of societies rather than on genuinely important objective features of the world. This seems to be a view that most people who accept the idea that race is socially constructed accept, though many augment this basic position with other philosophical theses.