Kris McDaniel

This Is Metaphysics


Скачать книгу

Classification and Properties

      1.51 Here is a natural train of thought. Things objectively belong together when they are similar in important ways. Things are similar in some way if and only if there is some way that those things all are. We call ways that things are properties. So, what it is for things to belong together is for them to share certain important properties.

      1.53 The question “What makes a property an important property?” matters if we assume both that there are some important properties and that there are some unimportant properties as well. But maybe the latter assumption is one that we shouldn’t make; maybe we should believe that the only properties that exist are the important properties. If the only properties that exist are the important properties, then we can say that things objectively belong together if and only if they have a property in common. This train of thought is less obviously on a circular track. We still need to face the question of what properties there are though.

      1.54 In order to address the question of what properties there are, it might be useful to have a quick discussion about how we attribute properties to things in ordinary language.

      1.55 Consider the sentence “Kris is short.” The subject of this sentence is the name “Kris.” The remainder of the sentence is the predicate “is short.” Very roughly, in general, a predicate is that part of a sentence which contains a verb and is used to state something about what is named by the subject of that sentence. Other examples: in the sentence, “Ranger is a dog,” “Ranger” is the subject and “is a dog” is the predicate; in the sentence “Ben eats French fries,” “Ben” is the subject and “eats French fries” is the predicate; in the sentence “José was an awesome teacher,” “José” is the subject and “was an awesome teacher” is the predicate. I hope this rough definition of the word “predicate” and the examples just mentioned have succeeded in giving you the idea of what a predicate is.

      1.57 So, we have a choice to make. One option is to believe that for every predicate, there is a corresponding property and some, but not all, of these properties are important, and then give a theory of what it is for a property to be an important property. Another option is to deny that every predicate corresponds to a property: on this option, although it is, for example, true of both Ranger and Mars that they are either dogs or planets, nonetheless there is no property of being a dog or a planet. On this second option we don’t obviously need a theory of when some property is an important property, since we can just say that all properties are important properties. (That said, if being an important property is something that comes in grades or degrees—if all properties are important but some important properties are more important than other important properties—then we still need a theory of grades or degrees of importance.) We do need a theory to tell us which predicates have properties corresponding to them. I suspect that on either option, the theories that we will give will look very similar to each other when they are fully developed, but I encourage you to see whether this suspicion ends up being correct. (We will further discuss the idea of an important property in Sections 2.4 and 2.9.)

      1.58 Here’s another idea worth considering: maybe we can’t define or explain what it is for some things to objectively belong together in terms of anything simpler. Instead of trying to define this concept, we could try to use it to define other concepts—such as, for example, the concept of an important property. It’s not clear to me how to do this, but that doesn’t mean this isn’t a project worth pursuing, especially since we already know that some expressions in our language can’t be explicitly defined.

      1.59 Either way, the metaphysics of classification and the metaphysics of properties are deeply connected. And so, if we want to know more about the former, it will help to know more about the latter. Chapter 2 will focus on the metaphysics of properties, although we will on occasion revisit some of the issues discussed in this chapter.

       We distinguished between subjective and objective ways of classifying objects. Are there other ways of classifying objects that aren’t neatly categorized as either subjective or objective?

       Are there degrees of objective belonging? That is, does it make sense to talk about quantities of objective belonging, for example, these objects belong to each other to degree n? If not, is there a best way to understand grades of objective belonging?

       Are there other classifications of people that seem at first to be objective but really are subjective? If so, what are they, and why do they seem (to at least some people) to be objective?

       How would you solve the new riddle of induction? Are there good solutions that don’t claim that some things objectively belong together?

       If not every predicate stands for a property, when does a predicate stand for a property?

      In addition to the readings I mentioned earlier in this chapter, here are some suggestions for further reading, along with very brief descriptions of them:

      1 Anjan Chakravartty (2011) “Scientific Realism and Ontological Relativity,” The Monist, vol. 94, no. 2, pp. 157–180.11This is an important paper on the metaphysics of classification from a perspective from the philosophy of science rather than metaphysics.

      2 Sally Haslanger (2012) Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique, Oxford: Oxford University Press.12This collection of essays contains important discussions of the metaphysics of social groups, including discussions of the metaphysics of race and gender.Ned Hall’s discussion of David Lewis’s views on the natural and non‐natural property distinction in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.13An important philosopher