Aviezer Tucker

Democracy Against Liberalism


Скачать книгу

Socialist, small holders, and Christian parties are often not populist. Mere anti-elitist rhetoric is insufficiently distinctive of populism.

      The political etymology of the term “populist” goes back to the late Roman Republic (133–27 BCE), when conflicts between the Optimates and Populares tore it apart in civil wars. Both groups were of elite Roman families, but the weaker clique sought popular support in its struggle with the stronger party that controlled the Roman Senate. The struggle was not so much between the people and the elites as between factions within the elite, some of whom did not shy away from attempting to use common people to support them. In response, the Optimates accused the Populares of demagoguery, the emotional manipulation of the political passions of the masses.

      Elite propaganda aside, the ancient Greek and Roman elites were just as likely as the lower classes to succumb to passions, both political and personal. Passions for social domination, economic rapaciousness, and arrogant condescension begot resentment and class warfare. The difference between the ancient classes was not marked by reason versus passion, but by different kinds of passions, different tastes for self-destructiveness, like the difference between single malt whiskey thrice distilled and industrial alcohol: consumed in sufficient quantities, they both kill, though at different price ranges and levels of smoothness. Elite and popular populisms fed on each other and led to mutual destruction in civil wars, the end of the republic.

      I adopt the core of the ancient concept of populism as the politics of passions, while rejecting its class bias, the exclusive association of the passions with lower classes. I propose to interpret populism, ancient and contemporary, as the rule of political passions. I maintain the ancient association of populism with passions and their manipulation by demagogues, but drop the class bias that associated populism exclusively with the politics of bread and circuses in Rome or beer and sausages in Marx’s view of the politics of the undisciplined poor, the Lumpenproletariat.

      The distinctions between passions, interests, and reason do not have to presume value judgments about which motivations are “legitimate” or “rational” and which are not. When the realization of passions comes at the expense of most other life projects, the passions are clearly and distinctly self-destructive. For example, irrespective of which life projects and goals jealous spouses may have, if they commit murder in jealous rage, whatever else they may have wished for, the rest of their lives will become impossible. Similarly, some economic policies give precedence to economic growth and social mobility, while others prefer economic equality and social cohesion. But populist policies, as in Venezuela, destroy the economy to an extent that growth and equality, mobility and cohesion, all become impossible.

      Not all passions are sufficiently extreme to be assuredly self-destructive. Some passions lead the people they motivate to take extreme risks, thereby increasing the probability, rather than certainty, of self-destruction. Political passionate recklessness may pay off when the populists who lead it are lucky. They may come to believe themselves invincible, smart, or empowered by their passions, until luck runs out.

      Populists tend to miss what Harry Frankfurte (1988, 11–25) called second-order volitions, a will to determine their own passions. Populists accept all their passions and do not recognize contradictions between the passions; the constraints that satisfying some imposes on satisfying others. Demagogue may enflame and manipulate passions, but cannot control them and would not try. Populist leaders must promise immediate gratification in the form of simple policy solutions that they may misrepresent as having no undesirable consequences. They cannot acknowledge the complexity of the world (Mounk 2018, 36–39). When populist leaders cannot gratify, they divert attention to something else. Populist passions demand policies that are incompatible and undermine each other. They necessitate more policies to correct those contradictions, and so on. This is most obvious in macro-economic policies that want to improve public services, reduce taxes, and keep inflation and the national debt down; or keep high levels of transfer payments from the young to the old, with low birth rates, and strict restrictions on immigration of young workers, as in Japan. Populist policies, as distinct from populist rhetoric or expressions of passion, eventually consume themselves in self-destructive bonfire of passions.