Steve Vanderheiden

Environmental Political Theory


Скачать книгу

the attendant urgency that these paragraphs suggest is appropriate. We cannot continue to deny the facts of scarcity or their relevance to our social and political ideals, as Locke could and did; nor can we continue to uncritically accept, as what John Stuart Mill called “dead dogma,”4 the many received ideas and ideals that have been constructed upon such a faulty foundation. So long as it remains possible to aspire toward enlightened or informed versions of those social and political ideals that have admirably guided human struggles against injustice in the past, we must subject them to critical examination in light of these facts, preserving what we can of them.

      In doing so, we must remain cognizant of the importance of such a project, but also of its limits. With abstract ideas like ecological limits, there can often be a significant lag between our recognition of the implications and force of an idea and its full incorporation into many of our other received ideas that were shaped by its absence. For many years, the aphorism “the solution to pollution is dilution” was repeated and internalized by those managing water resources, and was also routinely acted upon. Because ecological limits (in this case, the capacity of lakes or streams to assimilate waste) seemed sufficiently distant, those dumping their wastes in water might for decades have believed this convenient claim about cornucopian abundance. At some point, sensory evidence would belie the fiction as sewage and other waste began to harm the nonhuman users of polluted surface waters and then did the same to humans, with the resulting dissonance calling for some explanation.

      Abundance is a powerful myth, however. Long after we intellectually acknowledge that dilution isn’t really a “solution” to pollution created through human activity, human societies continue to act as if it is. The continued existence of an atmospheric commons that is almost entirely open to nearly unlimited greenhouse gas pollution, despite the ample observable indicators of dangerous climate change, attests to that power. Intellectual acknowledgment is one thing, but accommodating the ideas within our system of related ideas and practices is another and more daunting challenge. Ideas such as resource abundance, which allows for unlimited growth, can create a kind of path dependence through which they continue to exert influence long after they have been formally discredited, acting (to preview a term from chapter 5) as a kind of zombie, dead in some technical sense and yet still able to cause a zombie apocalypse alongside other ideas.

      An indirect legacy of this revival of the Malthusian tradition was a rift opened between the global North and South about who or what was most damaging to the global environment, with neo-Malthusians typically blaming rapid population growth in the global South (with what Hardin characterized as their “under-equipped lifeboats,” in reference to their high poverty rates and chronic food insecurity), while others faulted the high impacts of the global North’s patterns of industrialization and consumption. Its race and class dimensions added to the perception that environmentalism was an upper-middle-class white movement for affluent societies only, and the xenophobic pronouncements of neo-Malthusians calling for the withholding of famine aid and closed borders suggested a concern with the safeguarding of privilege rather than planetary stewardship. This image would persist for decades, with the idea of ecological limits motivating some misogynistic social views and heightening conflict and division within and between countries. Resource scarcity, that is, was held by some to vindicate or require wide and growing environmental inequality as the zero-sum nature of allocating finite resources forced uncomfortable choices about which claims to deny. As Hardin casts the dilemma through his lifeboat metaphor, to spare the global poor from deprivation by admitting them into one of the well-equipped boats of the global North would lead to global ecological ruin rather than confining this to the poor countries where it was, in his view, inevitable (as he writes: “The boat swamps, everyone drowns. Complete justice, complete catastrophe”).7

      Limits to growth make scarcity more palpable, and intensify conflict over increasingly scarce resources, awakening avarice and often leading to the abandonment of aspirations toward a more equitable society or world. Treating the world’s poor as drivers of overpopulation and ecological degradation, while denying them the agency needed to escape their fate without northern intervention, simultaneously patronized and infantilized entire peoples. Then, when the death toll fell short of the hundreds of millions over two decades that Ehrlich had predicted would starve in his 1968 The Population Bomb, charges of alarmism and intentional exaggeration became narratives for what still were (and continue to be) real and preventable humanitarian atrocities, with real ecological drivers.

      When Ehrlich’s apocalyptic prediction about famine deaths didn’t come to pass, skepticism about the idea, rather than urgency in meeting its challenges, was a common reaction. Ehrlich’s confidence