Tom McClelland

What is Philosophy of Mind?


Скачать книгу

also unlikely that propositional attitudes will provide a counter-example. A propositional attitude is about whatever figures in the proposition. It also looks like intentions are inevitably intentional (though not because of the superficial similarity of the terms). Intentions are directed at whatever they are intentions to do. Pains might cause more trouble. One might argue that pains aren’t really about anything – they just are. Emotions can also cause difficulties. Although emotions like Mindy’s elation have a clear intentional object, other emotions seem to be undirected. Your mood might be cheerful, or grumpy, or melancholy, yet none of these emotions need to be about anything in particular. Maybe we can say that these emotions are about the world in general but there would have to be good arguments for understanding them that way.

      The claim that intentionality is the mark of the mental certainly deserves to be taken seriously. But even if we stop short of advocating Brentano’s thesis, the foregoing provides us with something useful. First, it gives us some idea of how to draw the line between the mental and the non-mental, and thus of how to delineate the subject matter of philosophy of mind. Second, it gives us the valuable concept of intentionality to put in our conceptual toolkit. My initial sketch of what was going on in Mindy’s mind was a sketch of her perspective – her take on the world – with different mental states contributing to that perspective in their own distinctive ways. Understanding the mind will at least partly be a matter of understanding someone’s perspective, and we can apply that insight as we begin to explore the big questions that define the philosophy of mind.

      1 The Mind and Matter Question: What is the relationship between mind and matter?

      2 The Knowledge Question: How do we acquire knowledge of our own minds and the minds of others?

      3 The Distribution Question: Which things have minds and what kind of mind do they have?

      So what marks these out as the questions most deserving of our attention? Over the rest of this section, we’ll see that how we answer has important ramifications for how we answer the smaller questions. It’s hard to give an account of the nature of pain, for example, without taking a stance on the relationship between mind and matter. And over the rest of this book we’ll see that the most important theories in philosophy of mind are defined by how they answer the Big Questions. In fact, the whole history of philosophy of mind can helpfully be framed as the history of thought on these questions. With that in mind, let’s consider each question in turn.

       1.4.1 The Mind and Matter Question

      Materialists (aka physicalists) claim that there are no immaterial entities: that everything in the universe is constituted by the great material Lego set. Minds are no exception to this. Mindy’s mind is constituted by a material object – presumably her brain. The challenge for the materialist is to make sense of how this could be so. How can Mindy’s beliefs be a state of Mindy’s brain? How can her decisions be a neural process? How can her perceptions be a sparking of neurons? Dualists adopt the anti-materialist view that the world includes at least some immaterial entities, namely minds. Distinct from Mindy’s physical body is a non-physical mind – something that cannot be constituted by the physical building blocks described by physics. The challenge for the dualist is to make sense of where immaterial minds come from and how they’re connected to the brain.

      How we answer the Mind and Matter Question can have huge implications for how we see ourselves and how we live our lives. Do we have a special place in nature, standing apart from the world of material entities, or is the mind smoothly continuous with the rest of the material world? Do we come into existence when our brain comes into existence or might our minds predate our bodies? Do we die when our body dies or could the mind survive our bodily death? Are we really responsible for our actions or is our behaviour outside our control? Each of these urgent questions comes back to the core question of how mind and matter are related.

       1.4.2 The Knowledge Question

      It’s tempting to say that we know our own minds via a kind of inner sense. Just as Mindy knows what’s going on around her through perception, she knows what’s going on in her own mind through introspection. But what is this introspection and how does it work? We can also ask about how secure our self-knowledge is. Can you think you are in a mental state but be wrong? Perhaps Mindy can misidentify her nervousness as excitement, but it’s harder to make sense of her being wrong that she’s in pain. Can you be in a mental state without knowing that you are? We can make sense of Mindy having memories she doesn’t know about, but it’s harder to make sense of her failing to know that she’s in pain.

      What about our knowledge of other minds? Our knowledge of other minds seems less secure. Mindy knows her own intentions quite clearly but has a much harder time working out which way the goalkeeper intends to dive.