Группа авторов

Bioethics


Скачать книгу

XIII, 1 (1984): 24–54; and Lawrence C. Becker, “Human Being: The Boundaries of the Concept,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, IV, 4 (1975): 334–59.

      3 3 For example, see my “Ethics and the Elderly: Some Problems,” in Stuart Spicker, Kathleen Woodward, and David Van Tassel, eds., Aging and the Elderly: Humanistic Perspectives in Gerontology (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities, 1978), pp. 341–55.

      4 4 See Warren, “On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion,” and Tooley, “Abortion and Infanticide.”

      5 5 This seems to be the fatal flaw in Warren’s treatment of this issue.

      6 6 I have been most influenced on this matter by Jonathan Glover, Causing Death and Saving Lives (New York: Penguin, 1977), ch. 3; and Robert Young, “What Is So Wrong with Killing People?” Philosophy, LIV, 210 (1979): 515–28.

      7 7 Feinberg, Tooley, Warren, and Engelhardt have all dealt with this problem.

      8 8 Kant, “Duties to Animals and Spirits,” in Lectures on Ethics, trans. Louis Infeld (New York: Harper, 1963), p. 239.

      9 9 I am indebted to Jack Bricke for raising this objection.

      10 10 Presumably a preference utilitarian would press such an objection. Tooley once suggested that his account has such a theoretical underpinning. See his “Abortion and Infanticide,” pp. 44–5.

      11 11 Donald VanDeVeer seems to think this is self‐evident. See his “Whither Baby Doe?” in Matters of Life and Death, p. 233.

      12 12 “Must the Bearer of a Right Have the Concept of That to Which He Has a Right?” Ethics, XCV, 1 (1984): 68–74.

      13 13 See Tooley again in “Abortion and Infanticide,” pp. 47–9.

      14 14 “Present Sakes and Future Prospects: The Status of Early Abortion,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, XI, 4 (1982): 322–6.

      15 15 Note carefully the reasons he gives on the bottom of p. 316.

Part II Issues in Reproduction

      Introduction

      Developments in reproductive medicine have, over the past 50 years, presented us with remarkable new options, giving us increasing control over our fertility. Effective contraception and sterilization procedures have separated sex from reproduction, while various infertility treatments, such as in vitro fertilization, have dramatically increased the possibilities for reproduction without sex. Fertile couples are now able to limit and space the number of children they are going to have, while those who were once considered infertile are able to have children.

      There are also new opportunities to decide what our children will be like. Prenatal diagnosis of fetuses and testing of in vitro embryos allows prospective parents to decide not to bring a disabled child into the world, even without the use of abortion. (Those who accept the view defended by Patrick Lee and Rober P. George in the previous Part of this Anthology will not be mollified by a procedure that still involves the discarding of a viable human embryo.) The same techniques allow parents to select the sex of their child. Cloning and genetic modification of offspring are now possible for several species of mammals, and some think that it is only a matter of time before they take place in humans as well.

      A wide range of different issues are covered in this Part of the Anthology. Two interrelated clusters of questions, whilst by no means exhaustive of the ethical issues raised, are central to many of the discussions presented here: the limits, if any, to reproductive freedom, and the rights or interests of future children.

      Assisted Reproduction

      Being unable to have children can be a source of profound grief and great unhappiness. But some widely accepted technologies and procedures for overcoming infertility continue to raise troubling ethical issues. Fertility drugs given to women to enhance the production of eggs can lead to multiple pregnancies. When a woman carries more than one fetus, infants are frequently born prematurely and, if not stillborn, may have to spend long periods in neonatal intensive care. There is also an increased risk of brain damage and other serious disabilities.

      One outcome of the new reproductive techniques is that they make it easier for same‐sex couples to have children who are genetically related to at least one of them.

      A few years ago, to discuss the provision of assisted reproduction to same‐sex couples would have been pushing the frontiers of what is socially acceptable.

      With increasing acceptance of same‐sex marriage, and of the rights of same‐sex couples to have children, however, the use of assisted reproduction by same‐sex couples is increasing, and no longer seems as shocking as it once did. Timothy F. Murphy in “The Meaning of Synthetic Gametes for Gay and Lesbian People and Bioethics too” asks why so many ethical analyses of such technologies still treat same‐sex couples’ use of them as controversial, while the same questions are not raised when it comes to opposite‐sex couples. He responds to arguments defending the view that children ought to be conceived only under certain natural conditions, noting that there is no evidence that children who are conceived by other means are harmed in any way by the conditions of their conception and parentage.

      Other authors have argued that anonymous donor gametes are problematic because that option would separate children from their biological parents. David Velleman offers such an account. He thinks that without knowledge of one’s genetic parents children would suffer an information deficit in terms of what kind of life they could expect with genes like theirs. Murphy tackles this argument by pointing to the fact that children conceived of the synthetic gametes of a same‐sex couple would not actually suffer such an information deficit, and so new technologies could actually insist in overcoming the disadvantage Velleman is concerned about.

      Murphy concludes his analysis by addressing the objection from shared genetics. He rejects the idea that shared genetics is a necessary condition for good parenthood, agreeing instead with Thomas Murray, who argued that what makes for good parenthood is a moral commitment to one’s offspring.

      When controversial