Группа авторов

Bioethics


Скачать книгу

without qualification on opposite‐sex couples, subject only to the constraints of safety and efficacy of the intervention in question.

      As against commentators whose background assumptions throw gay and lesbian parenthood into question, some commentators explicitly reject the idea that same‐sex couples should be parents, at least not in any planned or socially approved way. Sometimes these objections focus on the nature of same‐sex couples as parents; other times the objections focus on the way in which same‐sex couples are able to have children.

      As part of her objections to legalising same‐sex marriage, Margaret Somerville has argued that giving the right to marry and to found a family ‘to same‐sex couples necessarily negates the rights of all (sic) children with respect to their biological origins and families, not just those born into same‐sex marriage’.10 She argues that same‐sex marriage violates a sexual ecology important to the welfare of children, and undermines a social symbolism essential in the transmission of life. In general, then, society should not endorse gay and lesbian couples having children through, for example, legal recognition of same‐sex marriage. Somerville wants society to endorse law and policies that enable children to be children of a woman whom they know as their mother and of a man whom they know as their father, as far as this effect is practically possible. This is not the entirety of her position, though, since she also argues that ‘children have a right to be conceived from untampered‐with biological origins, a right to be conceived from a natural sperm from one identified, living, adult man and a natural ovum from one identified, living, adult woman. Society should not be complicit in, that is, should not approve or fund any procedure for the creation of a child, unless the procedure is consistent with the child’s right to a natural biological heritage’.11 This position does not rule out all assisted reproduction, but it would put limits on it, including the use of synthetic gametes by same‐sex couples among others.

      Other commentators have also raised variations on the theme of harm that homosexual parents might inflict on their children. Abby Lippman and Stuart A. Newman worry that same‐sex couples will see embryos produced with their synthetic and naturally produced gametes as ‘assemblages’ and feel less responsibility toward them.13 Giuseppe Testa and John Harris correctly reply to this claim by noting that same‐sex couples who expend the time and effort to have children with shared genetics will likely exhibit a strong sense of responsibility and attachment toward the embryos and children in question.14 Given the moral and social history of suspicion toward homosexuality in general, it is perhaps easy to believe that gay and lesbian parents might have diminished capacities as parents, but the actual evidence shows no such effect, and there is no reason to assume a novel means of conception will change matters.12

      David Velleman has put some de facto obstacles in the way of gay men and lesbians having children through ARTs. He raises objections to the use of anonymous donor gametes and embryos, saying that children, in general, should not be separated from their biological parents.15 He holds that access to parents and other relatives, and knowledge about their lives, is a necessary condition of children’s development and fulfilment. On this view, one’s genetic relatives function as experiments of what one can do in life with genetics like one’s own. Without that knowledge, children necessarily suffer a deficit in self‐knowledge that is essential to self‐formation. It is better, then, that children not be dissociated from their genetic parents and relatives so far as practical. Not all ARTs go forward with anonymous gametes and embryos, of course, but some do, and Velleman’s approach raises a bar against any and all parentage by gay men and lesbians that relies on those treatments.

      By contrast with anonymous gamete donation, synthetic gametes would give children of same‐sex couples what Velleman wants from parental and familial relationships in general. Barring the loss of their parents through death or divorce, children conceived with the natural and synthetic gametes of a gay couple would have available to them genetic relatives on Partner A’s side, namely grandparents, aunts and uncles, and other relatives. The children would also have available to them the same gamut of genetic relatives for Partner B. Neither partner, in this case, would function as a genetically identified or socially identified female. Yet, both the parents and their relatives would be available, at least in principle, to the child in providing examples of how to live and how the child might put his or her own similar genetic endowment to work in making choices in life. The same outcome holds for a child of a lesbian couple, conceived with natural and synthetic gametes.

      Velleman might try and argue that having two fathers (or two mothers) amounts to a deprivation visited upon the children, but this argument will not succeed because his view does not require any specific content to the lives of genetic relatives, only that their lives and strivings be available to the children as kinds of experimental results of living with a similar genetic endowment. A man who uses ova synthesised from his body to have children is no less an instructional blueprint for living than someone living as a woman who uses her natural ova to have children. In the end, Velleman’s arguments about access to genetic parents and relatives lend support to the idea of same‐sex couples turning to synthetic gametes to have children. At the very least, the concern about the supposed ill effects of anonymous gamete donation could be bypassed and rendered moot.

      I will mention one last possible objection to the use of synthetic gametes