Группа авторов

Bioethics


Скачать книгу

a doctor removes a person’s limb to save his life. It would not be true, at least in a morally relevant sense, that the doctor harmed this person, or affected him for the worse. We seem bound to say the same about my second woman.

      The acts which I have described are of course unusual. But this does not make them a worse test for the person‐affecting restriction. On the contrary, they are unusual because they are designed as a test. The two women’s acts are designed to be as similar as they could be, except in one respect. Each woman deliberately brings it about that she has a disabled rather than a normal child. The only difference is that in one case the disabled and the normal child are the same child, while in the other they are not. This is precisely the difference which, on the person‐affecting principle, matters. If we think that the two acts would be just as wrong, we cannot believe that it does matter.

      When we turn to population policy, the implications become much harder to accept….

      [Editorial note: the rest of Parfit’s talk is not reprinted here. His more recent thoughts about the problems discussed in this talk, and the larger problems of population policy, will appear in a future issue of the journal, Philosophy & Public Affairs, under the title “Overpopulation.”]

      Notes

      1 1 Cf. Michael Tooley, “Abortion and Infanticide,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 2, No. 1 (Fall 1972) [see chapter 1 in this Anthology].

      2 2 Quoted in G. Tedeschi, “On Tort Liability for ‘Wrongful Life,’ ” Israel Law Review, October 1966, p. 514, footnote 3.

      3 3 The logic he describes in his books, The Language of Morals, OUP, 1952, and Freedom and Reason, OUP, 1963.

      4 4 For a legal discussion of related issues, see “A Cause of Action for ‘Wrongful Life,’ ” Minnesota Law Review, 55, No. 1 (November 1970).

      5 5 This asymmetry is discussed in Jan Narveson’s two articles: “Utilitarianism and New Generations,” Mind, January 1967, and “Moral Problems of Population,” The Monist, January 1973. I have learned much from both of these.

      6 6 For a different view, take a remark in Gwen Raverat’s Period Piece, Faber and Faber, 1952, “It is always a fascinating problem to consider who we would have been if our mother (or our father) had married another person.”

      7 7 “Making babies – the new biology and the ‘old’ morality,” Leon Kass, The Public Interest, Winter, 1972.

Prenatal Screening, Sex Selection, and Cloning

       Laura M. Purdy

      Is it morally permissible for me to have children? A decision to procreate is surely one of the most significant decisions a person can make. So it would seem that it ought not be made without some moral soul‐searching.

      There are many reasons why one might hesitate to bring children into this world if one is concerned about their welfare. Some are rather general, such as the deteriorating environment or the prospect of poverty. Others have a narrower focus, such as continuing civil war in one’s country or the lack of essential social support for child‐rearing in the United States. Still others may be relevant only to individuals at risk of passing harmful diseases to their offspring.

      Unsurprisingly, most of the debate about this issue has focused on prenatal screening and abortion: much useful information about a given fetus can be made available by recourse to prenatal testing. This fact has meant that moral questions about reproduction have become entwined with abortion politics, to the detriment of both. The abortion connection has made it especially difficult to think about whether it is wrong to prevent a child from coming into being, because doing so might involve what many people see as wrongful killing; yet there is no necessary link between the two. Clearly, the existence of genetically compromised children can be prevented not only by aborting already existing fetuses but also by preventing conception in the first place.