Группа авторов

Bioethics


Скачать книгу

itself, or of the direction of medicine. Nor is it that the ethics employed are abstract and have to conform to the discourse rules of bioethics, which forbid historical analysis of social processes, such as the trend of objectification and the forces driving it. The problem is worse: the HFEA cannot even articulate the basic ethical issues at the centre of public concern.

      Surveying the HFEA’s public statements on the Whitaker case we find two arguments: the potential psychological effect for Jamie, and the risk of PGD to the embryo, which can only be justified if there is benefit to that embryo, i.e. being assured of not suffering from a genetic disorder. The latter argument is the basis of the HFEA’s permitting the Hashmi family to undergo embryo selection. Their child Zain suffers from thalassemia, a genetic disease, so they could argue that their primary purpose for PGD was to prevent the new child having thalassemia, and that tissue type selection would add no extra risk to the embryo. The HFEA turned down the Whitakers last year because their son was suffering from a disorder which is not genetic, and there is therefore no case for using PGD to avoid it.

      More importantly, nowhere in the HFEA’s public pronouncements can we find any clear reference to the point, which has been at the centre of the public debate, about the Kantian ethical principle of non‐instrumentalisation/objectification. Now even the rules of liberal ethics cannot be publicly mentioned. How can this be? The answer is that the HFEA is, by virtue of its own institutional nature, not allowed to use the sort of ethical principles that ordinary people use. It can consider medical benefit and risk and, because it is written into the relevant legislation, the welfare of the child. But for the HFEA, which has legal responsibilities, and exists in a controversial and litigious climate, it is impossible to base its decision even on ethical principles as universally accepted as Kant’s, because to do so makes it vulnerable: only benefit, risk and welfare considerations, on a strictly individual case‐by‐case basis, are legally defensible. (The Whitaker/Hashmi distinction, for example, is not based on any real moral difference between the cases; in the Whitaker case the HFEA overruled its own ethics committee, which wanted to be consistent with its decision on the Hashmis. What dictated the HFEA decision in these cases was the need to stay within the letter of the law, which appears to forbid selection of embryos to benefit another individual. Its calculation was correct, and allowed it to defend its decision in the High Court against a pro‐life group’s challenge. In effect they made the right decision for the wrong reasons. This is one more example of sensible policy and decision making being tripped up by accidents of drafting of the 1990 HFE Act: it has been comprehensively overtaken by developments in science and technology and needs amending.)

      So the result of the HFEA’s institutional status is that the key ethical decision‐making body in this area is forced to behave as an ethical illiterate, and to operate ethically on the basis of political pragmatism. This will never lead to decisions that are either principled or in the public interest.

      What is happening is strikingly reminiscent of the history of genetically modified organisms (GMOs): that experience should be a warning to the government. Throughout the 1990s critics complained that the Advisory Committee on Release to the Environment (ACRE) based judgements about the environmental risk of GMOs on narrow, case‐by‐case analyses of the direct environmental impact of small‐scale experimental trials, without considering wider issues. It did so because of the narrow definition of environmental harm in the 1990 Environmental Protection Act. ACRE was not permitted to consider the impact of GMOs in farming (eg. changes in patterns of pesticide use created by GMO use) which might have large environmental impacts, let alone the wider implications of GMOs. Its members had a narrow range of scientific expertise, with no sociologist, economist or expert in farming and the environment. So it could not address many concerns of environmentalists and other critics, yet it was the main venue of regulatory decisions which, by government dogma, must be ‘science‐based’. These concerns eventually exploded into direct action and public furore. ACRE was completely overhauled, European law was rewritten, and the government was forced to delay while it mounted farm‐scale trials of the impact of GMOs.

      The HFEA is in essentially the same position as ACRE in the 1990s. Its legal responsibilities stop it from addressing the public’s real concerns, about the trends of objectification, consumerism and eugenics, and where these technologies, step by step, are taking us. As long as HFEA continues to work this way, the head of steam will continue to build, and who knows how it will be released.

      Ultimately, an adequate ethical discourse needs to reassess the dominant imperative to eliminate all disease and suffering, and the moral blackmail which is wielded at those who dare to suggest that other concerns might have equal importance. For if we fail to do so, we will find, not so far in the future, that the consequences of abandoning principle after principle will be felt not only in terms of a moral vacuum, but in the profound suffering of real human beings, in ways that we can now only begin to imagine.

       Michael Tooley

      Cloning human organisms may have quite different goals. The object may be to produce a human organism that will develop into a normal person. Alternatively, the goal may be to produce a human embryo for scientific research purposes, or as a source of stem cells to be used in medical treatments. Yet another possibility is the creation of a human to serve as a future organ bank for some presently existing person. In this essay, I shall consider whether cloning is or is not morally permissible in each of these three cases.

      1.1 John Locke’s concept of a person

      In chapter 27 of An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, John Locke (1632–1704) discussed the idea of identity, and there he distinguished between the identity of a man – that is, of a human animal – and the identity of a person. As regards the former, Locke’s view was as follows:

      This also shows wherein the identity of the same man consists: viz. in nothing but a participation of the same continued life, by constantly fleeting particles of matter, in succession vitally united to the same organized body. (chap. 27, para. 6)

      As regards the concept of a person, however, Locke offered a very different account: