Группа авторов

Bioethics


Скачать книгу

have attacked GLGT and GLGE on the grounds that they constitute a form of eugenics, an attempt to control the human gene pool.69 Is eugenics inherently wrong? To understand this question, we can distinguish between positive and negative eugenics: positive eugenics attempts to increase the number of favorable or desirable genes in the human gene pool, while negative eugenics attempts to reduce the number of undesirable or harmful genes, e.g., genes that cause genetic diseases. We should also distinguish between state‐sponsored and parental eugenics: under state‐sponsored eugenics programs the government attempts to control the human gene pool; in parental eugenics parents exert control over the gene pool through their reproductive choices.70

      But what about state‐sponsored eugenics? One might argue that state‐sponsored eugenics programs, such as involuntary sterilization of the mentally disabled or mandatory genetic screening, are morally wrong because they:

      1 constitute unjustifiable violations of individual liberty and privacy;

      2 are a form of genetic discrimination;

      3 can have adverse evolutionary consequences by reducing genetic diversity; and

      4 can lead us down a slippery slope toward increased racial and ethnic hatred, bias, and genocide.

      Having said this much, I think some forms of enhancement can be morally justified, provided that they can be shown to be safe and effective. For example, using genetic technology to protect people against diseases could be justified on the grounds that it benefits patients. I think one can even justify the use of genetics for cosmetic purposes in terms of benefits to patients. We can also view some forms of genetic therapy as unacceptable (at present) because they pose unjustifiable risks to patients or future generations. For example, all forms of GLGT and some types of SGT, such as a procedure for fighting cancer at the genetic level, are too risky, given our current scientific and technical limitations. In any case, the moral assessment of these procedures depends on considerations of probable benefits and harms (as well as other moral qualities), not on their classification as “therapy” or “enhancement.”

      Notes

      1 1 Juengst E. Can enhancement be distinguished from prevention in genetic medicine? Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1997; 22: 125–42.

      2 2 Holtug N. Altering humans – the case for and against human gene therapy. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 1997; 6: 157–74.

      3 3 Berger E., and Gert B. Genetic disorders and the ethical status of germ‐line gene therapy. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1991; 16: 667–83.

      4 4 Anderson W. Human gene therapy: scientific and ethical considerations. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1985; 10: 275–91.

      5 5 Anderson W. Human gene therapy: why draw a line? Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1989; 14: 81–93.

      6 6 Anderson W. Genetics and human malleability. Hastings Center Report 1990; 20(1): 21–4.

      7 7 McGee G. The Perfect Baby. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1997.

      8 8 Vogel G. Genetic enhancement: from science fiction to ethics quandary. Science 1997; 277: 1753–4.

      9 9 See note 4, Anderson 1985.

      10 10 Fowler G, Juengst E, and Zimmerman B. Germ‐line gene therapy and the clinical ethos of medical genetics. Theoretical Medicine 1989; 19: 151–7.

      11 11 See note 3, Berger and Gert 1991.

      12 12 Zimmerman B. Human germ‐line gene therapy: the case for its development and use. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1991; 16: 593–612.

      13