Группа авторов

A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value


Скачать книгу

      I believe there is a deeper explanation, which is that, in nature aesthetics, there has been a long-standing undercurrent of suspicion, not to say hostility, toward mediated appreciation in general. By “mediated appreciation” of nature, I mean appreciation that occurs not through direct or “in person” perception of nature, but through experience of a representation of nature. In this paper, I examine this opposition and argue that, while mediated appreciation of nature does involve certain dangers, these have largely been exaggerated, and have led to an unfortunate neglect of film by nature aesthetics. Furthermore, I’ll argue that considering film in fact helps to defuse these very worries about mediated appreciation. This is important, because mediated appreciation constitutes an important and under-studied dimension of the aesthetic appreciation of nature. Furthermore, film’s capacity to mediate nature appreciation reveals an important aspect of its role as a public artform: by reshaping our relationship to natural beauty, film has the potential to alter both the public’s understanding of environmental value and its behavior with respect to the environment.

      Mediated Appreciation

      That photographs of people and everyday objects can be appreciatively apt seems clear. But what about representations of other things? Consider art: just as we use photographs to appreciate people’s looks, so we also use them to appreciate works of art. A photograph of Degas’ L’Etoile is different from, and does not fully substitute for, the artwork in the Louvre: the size is obviously different, for example; the texture of the paint and the brushstrokes may not be evident in the photograph; and the glossy sheen of a photographic reproduction is not a property of the original canvas. Nonetheless, reproductions do present to us many of the work’s features, such as the composition of shapes and colors on the canvas, and we can appreciate the work’s aesthetic achievement, to some degree, on that basis. Another familiar example of appreciating art in a mediated way is listening to a recording of a live vocal performance: the recording presents to us some of the relevant qualities of the performance, and thereby allows us to appreciate it (again, to some degree) without directly perceiving it (Semczyszyn 2013b).

      These cases of mediated appreciation of artworks are familiar and commonplace, and they do play an important role in our appreciation of art. Our culture’s aesthetic appreciation of painting would be very different, were it not for the existence of photographic reproduction. Nonetheless, mediated appreciation seems to have only a secondary importance in the appreciation of art. Direct perceptual experience remains the paradigm, with reproductions being used only for convenience, and themselves raising no theoretical puzzles.

      In the case of mediated appreciation of nature, however, we find matters somewhat inverted. Here mediated experience plays a much more central role than it does in our appreciation of art: most of us have never seen, or will ever see, a polar bear in its Arctic habitat, the Great Barrier Reef, or a Sahara desert landscape. If we have any aesthetic access to these at all, it is an access mediated via representations such as photos, paintings, film, and literary narratives. Indeed, there are some parts of nature that can only be appreciated through representations, for practical or prudential reasons, such as the ocean floor and the far side of the moon.

      Ecological considerations can also confer particular importance on mediated nature appreciation. Consider Sable Island: a remote sandy strip of land about 300 km off the eastern shore of Canada. It’s a striking landscape with a unique natural history and a fragile ecology: a 40-kilometer-long sandbar whose dunes, continually blasted by the winds of the North Atlantic, are held together by vegetation. Until recently, access to the island was restricted by the Canadian government, since trampling of the island’s native grasses poses a threat to dune stability and hence the very existence of the island. To the extent that anyone knew the beauty of the place at all, it was through photographs and films, such as those created in the 1990s by the photographer Roberto Dutesco, who obtained permission to visit the island and photograph its population of wild horses. In cases such as this, direct appreciation would come at a real environmental cost (for more on this case, see Parsons 2015).

      Philosophers on Meditated Nature Appreciation

      Over the last 50 years, there has been much philosophical discussion about various aspects of our practices of aesthetically appreciating nature. In these debates, some big differences have emerged, one of which concerns the role of scientific understanding in aesthetic appreciation. Some thinkers have insisted that the aesthetic appreciation of nature should be informed by our best understanding of nature and its history, just as our aesthetic appreciation of art must be informed by our best understanding of art and its history. The thought is that, just as to properly appreciate, say, a Cubist painting, one needs to understand the history and nature of that genre, so to appreciate a part of nature properly one needs the relevant historical and contextual knowledge about that part of nature. And such relevant historical and contextual knowledge about nature is to be found in our scientific understanding of it (Carlson 1979a). Others have rejected this requirement, eschewing any such normative constraint on nature appreciation. All that is needed to properly appreciate nature, some maintain, is careful attention and sensitivity to the features it displays in our perception of it: its striking forms and colors, its moving events, intriguing processes and so on.

      This division represents perhaps the main ideological split in the field (for a general discussion, see Parsons 2008; Carlson 2019). Despite this deep division, however, one thing that thinkers on both sides of the division share is a neglect of, if not contempt toward, mediated appreciation of nature.

      Consider first the leading representative of the view that nature appreciation should be informed by scientific understanding, Allen Carlson. Broaching the general question of how we ought to aesthetically appreciate nature, Carlson takes as his key insight the idea that nature is an environment. This means, in his view, that nature is not any particular object or set of objects before or around us, but rather the whole background setting in which we, and the objects around us, are enveloped. Thus, Carlson writes: “the beginning of an answer as to how to aesthetically appreciate an environment is something like the following. We must experience our background setting in all those ways in which we normally experience it, by sight, smell, touch and whatever” (1979a, 272).

      Having set up the idea of appreciating nature in this way, Carlson goes on to draw a strong contrast between this paradigm of direct sensory engagement of the environment and appreciation mediated by representations of nature, such as photographs. He writes: