Edmund Neill

Conservatism


Скачать книгу

or covertly, to try to render more progressive alternatives illegitimate.

      However, there are also two problems with this definition. First, as we have seen, it is not always true that conservatives content themselves with the strategy of trying to ensure that historical change occurs in a cautious and evolutionary fashion. Rather, in some instances, conservatives themselves seek to initiate change, sometimes of a radical kind, with the aim of restoring a previous status quo. (For example, as noted earlier, an important component of the conservatism of the Thatcher and Reagan governments was their attempt to reverse developments they regarded as illegitimate, not least those associated with rises in direct taxation and the expansion of the welfare state.) Second, although the attempt by conservatives to present their approach to tradition as uniquely ‘natural’ or perceptive may well be revealing of their ideological strategy, it cannot be accepted as an objective analysis of conservatism. For whether or not conservatives are convincing in their particular interpretations of tradition and their responses to it, what they advocate cannot simply be assumed to be ‘natural’; rather, as with all such responses to tradition, this is a claim that must be argued for.

      These are, first, the unification of societies, so that discrete, self-contained social units are joined together, often within the nation-state; second, that within such unified societies there develop differing social strata, some favouring progress, while others favour reaction; third, that divergent ‘worlds of ideas’ corresponding to these different strata also appear; and fourth, that these divergences increasingly take on an explicitly political character – so that the struggle between progressive ideas and those of reaction are increasingly fought out in an explicitly political sphere (Mannheim 1986: 83–6). All of these related developments mean that those seeking to preserve older social and political structures can no longer simply assume their worth and durability, but instead must explicitly argue for them. Hence the appearance, Mannheim argued, of a self-conscious conservatism,6 which has two key features.

      In suggesting that conservatism is best defined as an explicitly modern phenomenon that specifically emerges to combat the effects of sociological changes and progressive ideologies associated with the French Revolution, Mannheim provided a more promising definition than those who seek to identify conservatism with a backward-looking nostalgia or an adherence to a single natural, hegemonic, tradition. Moreover, his observation that conservatives have often sought to rebut progressives’ arguments by contending that their abstract concepts are better defined in concrete and historically situated terms provides a valuable insight into how conservatism operates. However, given Mannheim’s focus on conservatism’s origins, what his account lacks is a full account of how conservatism develops, and in particular of what provides it with lasting coherence as it has evolved and mutated from its beginnings in the late eighteenth century to the present.

      How, then, does Freeden think that conservatism functions as a political ideology, and what does he believe its ‘core concepts’ to be? Echoing some of