Edmund Neill

Conservatism


Скачать книгу

of other conceptual vocabulary, whether this be as varieties of the political ‘Right’ – such as ‘moderate Right’, ‘radical Right’, ‘extreme Right’ – or in terms of other vocabulary altogether, such as ‘Christian democrat’, ‘romantic’ or ‘reactionary’. This of course does not preclude making distinctions between different types of conservatism. There are, for example, important differences of emphasis between those forms of conservatism that tend to favour a more active attempt to return politics and society to an earlier point; those that are pessimistic about the current prospects for successful adaptation without the survival of earlier norms, but see little prospect of retaining or resuscitating them; and those that are more cautiously optimistic. One may even contend that Freeden should have made more of these differences of emphasis in his analysis. But this should not detract from his major achievement in establishing that all such ideological positions are ultimately species of conservatism, rather than being radically separate forms of right-wing thinking.8 What Freeden’s approach provides, in other words, is a way of identifying what differentiates conservatism from other ideological positions while also respecting its extreme adaptability.

      1  1 For just one example, see Nisbet 1986: 21–74; see also Freeden 1996: 331–2.

      2  2 Ironically, Huntington did not in fact himself remain loyal to his definition of conservatism as essentially reactive, also claiming that ‘the essence of conservatism can be summed up in a small number of basic ideas’ (Huntington 1957: 457).

      3  3 See below, Chapters 2 and 5, and Gray 1997a.

      4  4 See below, Chapter 2.

      5  5 It is true that to some extent Oakeshott and Gilmour both admitted that a conservative approach to tradition was more complex than this. Oakeshott, in particular, especially in his later work, emphasized that a tradition is not a monolithic entity, but instead composed of a set of diverse practices (see, for example, Oakeshott 1975: 55–60 and Oakeshott 1976). This did not, however, dislodge Oakeshott from his fundamental conviction that there is a dominant tendency within the Western European tradition favouring individualism. As such, he believed those opposing it were not merely in disagreement, but mistaken (Oakeshott 1991: 363–83).

      6  6 See Mannheim: ‘the conservative mode of experience thus preserves itself … by raising to the level of reflection and methodical control those attitudes to the world which would otherwise have been lost to authentic experience’ (1986: 101).

      7  7 Although conservatism apparently advocates a huge variety of different positions, Freeden argues that as an ideology it does much more than simply provide a knee-jerk reaction to progressive ideologies at any given moment, as Huntington would contend. Rather, while it deploys political concepts more eclectically than progressive ideologies do, it does not do so in a purely reactive manner, but instead seeks to establish counter-progressive positions which may have considerable potential to endure.

      8  8 Compare, by contrast, the approach taken by Eatwell and O’Sullivan (1989) on ‘the nature of the Right’.

      9  9 It should be emphasized that I am definitely not implying that conservatism is a uniquely Western phenomenon