Edmund Neill

Conservatism


Скачать книгу

one can with the more ‘progressive’ ideologies of liberalism and socialism, since the ideological commitments of conservatives have been so variable. Rather, he seeks to build upon the more historically focused analyses of conservatism that we examined above, but to combine them into a more sophisticated structure. He argues that conservative ideology has four ‘core’ concepts – which of course can be combined with various (often more substantive) ‘adjacent’ and ‘peripheral’ ones. The core concepts are, first, a commitment to controlling or managing historical change, which at the very least favours caution in altering the status quo over radical change, and may (more ambitiously) claim that only change in accordance with ‘natural’ development or an ‘organic tradition’ should be considered legitimate. Freeden thus picks up Oakeshott’s and Gilmour’s arguments about conservatives following a ‘natural’ tradition, but treats these as a statement of conservative ideology, rather than as objective descriptions about tradition and historical change (Freeden 1996: 332–3).

      This helps to explain the variability of such concepts within conservatism, Freeden argues, since on the face of it conservatives appear to be fundamentally inconsistent, variously advocating the importance of aristocratic hierarchy, mass democracy, income inequality and relatively generous welfare states. But in fact, these radical inconsistencies become readily explicable if they are viewed as subsidiary to the core conservative desires to control change and treat human agency as subject to an ‘extra-human’ order, since such adjacent conservative concepts are always constituted as responses to progressivism, just in divergent ways at different times (Freeden 1996: 335–40). Indeed, Freeden emphasizes, it is important to stress that conservatives’ formulation of such concepts is far from being a passive process; rather, they are chosen precisely to combat whichever ‘threat’ to the current social and political order seems most pressing. (To give just one of Freeden’s examples, in mid-nineteenth-century Britain, Victorian conservatives sought to combat liberal demands for more equal rights, particularly voting rights, by stressing the importance of a pre-existing aristocratic order for ensuring social and political stability; by the early twentieth century, however, they were instead stressing the virtues of universal private property rights against incipient demands for socialist redistribution [Freeden 1996: 339–40].) Paradoxically, Freeden argues, this can mean that if progressive demand for change is particularly strong, conservative support for the status quo can harden into conceptual rigidity, since although in the longer term a major strength of conservatism is its adaptability, in the shorter term the form conservatism takes is always parasitic on its progressive opponents (Freeden 1996: 341–2).7

      One major advantage of such an approach