Группа авторов

Bioethics


Скачать книгу

in which one lives. Herodotus tells how Darius, King of Persia, summoned the Greeks from the western shores of his kingdom before him, and asked them how much he would have to pay them to eat their fathers’ dead bodies. They were horrified by the idea and said they would not do it for any amount of money, for it was their custom to cremate their dead. Then Darius called upon Indians from the eastern frontiers of his kingdom, and asked them what would make them willing to burn their fathers’ bodies. They cried out and asked the King to refrain from mentioning so shocking an act. Herodotus comments that each nation thinks its own customs best. From here it is only a short step to the view that there can be no objective right or wrong, beyond the bounds of one’s own culture. This view found increased support in the nineteenth century as Western anthropologists came to know many different cultures, and were impressed by ethical views very different from those that were standardly taken for granted in European society. As a defense against the automatic assumption that Western morality is superior and should be imposed on “savages,” many anthropologists argued that, since morality is relative to culture, no culture can have any basis for regarding its morality as superior to any other culture.

      Although the motives with which anthropologists put this view forward were admirable, they may not have appreciated the implications of the position they were taking. The ethical relativist maintains that a statement like “It is good to enslave people from another tribe if they are captured in war” means simply “In my society, the custom is to enslave people from another tribe if they are captured in war.” Hence if one member of the society were to question whether it really was good to enslave people in these circumstances, she could be answered simply by demonstrating that this was indeed the custom – for example, by showing that for many generations it had been done after every war in which prisoners were captured. Thus there is no way for moral reformers to say that an accepted custom is wrong – “wrong” just means “in accordance with an accepted custom.”

      On the other hand, when people from two different cultures disagree about an ethical issue, then according to the ethical relativist there can be no resolution of the disagreement. Indeed, strictly there is no disagreement. If the apparent dispute were over the issue just mentioned, then one person would be saying “In my country it is the custom to enslave people from another tribe if they are captured in war” and the other person would be saying “In my country it is not the custom to allow one human being to enslave another.” This is no more a disagreement than such statements as “In my country people greet each other by rubbing noses” and “In my country people greet each other by shaking hands.” If ethical relativism is true, then it is impossible to say that one culture is right and the other is wrong. Bearing in mind that some cultures have practiced slavery, or the burning of widows on the funeral pyre of their husbands, this is hard to accept.

      It might seem that ruling out particular terms in this way does not take us very far. After all, one can always describe oneself in universal terms. Perhaps I can’t say that everyone should do what is in my interests, but I could say that everyone must do whatever is in the interests of people who … and then give a minutely detailed description of myself, including the precise location of all my freckles. The effect would be the same as saying that everyone should do what is in my interests, because there would be no one except me who matches that description. Hare meets this problem by saying that to prescribe an ethical judgment universally means being prepared to prescribe it for all possible circumstances, including hypothetical ones. So if I were to say that everyone should do what is in the interests of a person with a particular pattern of freckles, I must be prepared to prescribe that in the hypothetical situation in which I do not have this pattern of freckles, but someone else does, I should do what is in the interests of that person. Now of course I may say that I should do that, since I am confident that I shall never be in such a situation, but this simply means that I am being dishonest. I am not genuinely prescribing the principle universally.

      The effect of saying that an ethical judgment must be universalizable for hypothetical as well as actual circumstances is that whenever I make an ethical judgment, I can be challenged to put myself in the position of the parties affected, and see if I would still be able to accept that judgment. Suppose, for example, that I own a small factory and the cheapest way for me to get rid of some waste is to pour it into a nearby river. I do not take water from this river, but I know that some villagers living downstream do and the waste may make them ill. If I imagine myself in the hypothetical situation of being one of the villagers, rather than the factory‐owner, I would not accept that the profits of the factory‐owner should outweigh the risk of adverse effects on my health and that of my children. Hence I cannot claim that I am ethically justified in polluting the river.

      In this way Hare’s approach introduces an element of reasoning in ethical deliberation. For Hare, however, since universalizability is part of the logic of moral language, an amoralist can avoid it by simply avoiding making any ethical judgments. More recently, several prominent moral philosophers, among them Thomas Nagel, T.M. Scanlon, and Derek Parfit have defended the view that we have objective reasons for action. Ethical judgments, in their view, are not statements of fact, but can nevertheless be true or false, in the same way that the truths of logic, or mathematics, are not statements of fact, but can be true or false. It is true, they would argue, that if someone is in agony, and we can relieve that agony, we have a reason for doing so. If we can relieve it at no cost, or a very low cost, to ourselves or anyone else, we will have a conclusive reason for relieving it, and it will be wrong not to do so.

      The questions we have been discussing so far are questions about ethics, rather than questions within ethics. Philosophers call this “metaethics” and distinguish it from “normative ethics” in which we discuss what we ought to do. Normative ethics can also be divided into two parts, ethical theory and applied ethics. As we noted at the beginning of this introduction, bioethics is an area of applied ethics. Ethical theory, on the other hand, deals with broad ethical theories about how we ought to live and act, and we will now outline some of the more important of these theories.

      The utilitarian view is striking in many ways. It puts forward a single principle that it claims can provide the right answer to all ethical dilemmas, if only we can predict what the consequences of our actions will be. It takes ethics out of the mysterious realm of duties and rules, and bases ethical decisions on something that almost everyone understands and values. Moreover, utilitarianism’s single principle is applied universally, without fear or favor. Bentham said: “Each to count for one and none for more than one.” By that he meant that the happiness of a peasant counted for as much as that of a noble, and the happiness of an African was no less important than that of a European – a progressive view