Группа авторов

Bioethics


Скачать книгу

is, however, whether we can have a notion of what a virtuous person would do in a specific situation without making a prior decision about what it is right to do. After all, in any particular moral dilemma, different virtues may be applicable, and even a particular virtue will not always give unequivocal guidance. For instance, if a terminally ill patient repeatedly asks a nurse or doctor for assistance in dying, what response best exemplifies the virtues of a healthcare professional? There seems no answer to this question, short of an inquiry into whether it is right or wrong to help a patient in such circumstances to die. But in that case we seem bound, in the end, to come back to discussing such issues as whether it is right to follow moral rules or principles, or to do what will have the best consequences.

      In the late twentieth century, some feminists offered new criticisms of conventional thought about ethics. They argued that the approaches to ethics taken by the influential philosophers of the past – all of whom have been male – give too much emphasis to abstract principles and the role of reason, and give too little attention to personal relationships and the part played by emotion. One outcome of these criticisms has been the development of an “ethic of care,” which is not so much a single ethical theory as a cluster of ways of looking at ethics which put an attitude of caring for others at the center, and seek to avoid reliance on abstract ethical principles. The ethic of care has seemed especially applicable to the work of those involved in direct patient care. Not all feminists, however, support this development. Some worry that presenting an ethic of care in opposition to a “male” ethic based on reasoning reflects and reinforces stereotypes of women as more emotional and less rational than men. They also fear that it could lead to women continuing to carry a disproportionate share of the burden of caring for others.

      To say that ethics is independent of religion is not to deny that theologians or other religious believers may have a role to play in bioethics. Religious traditions often have long histories of dealing with ethical dilemmas, and the accumulation of wisdom and experience that they represent can give us valuable insights into particular problems. But these insights should be subject to criticism in the way that any other proposals would be. If in the end we accept them, it is because we have judged them sound, not because they are the utterances of a pope, a rabbi, a mullah, or a holy person.

      Ethics is also independent of the law, in the sense that the rightness or wrongness of an act cannot be settled by its legality or illegality. Whether an act is legal or illegal may often be relevant to whether it is right or wrong, because it is arguably wrong to break the law, other things being equal. Many people have thought that this is especially so in a democracy, in which everyone has a say in making the law. Another reason why the fact that an act is illegal may be a rea‐ son against doing it is that the legality of an act may affect the consequences that are likely to flow from it. If active voluntary euthanasia is illegal, then doctors who practice it risk going to jail, which will cause them and their families to suffer, and also mean that they will no longer be able to help other patients. This can be a powerful reason for not practicing voluntary euthanasia when it is against the law, but if there is only a very small chance of the offense becoming known, then the weight of this consequentialist reason against breaking the law is reduced accordingly. Whether we have an ethical obligation to obey the law, and, if so, how much weight we should give it, is itself an issue for ethical argument.

      Though ethics is independent of the law, in the sense just specified, laws are subject to evaluation from an ethical perspective. Many debates in bioethics focus on questions about what practices should be allowed – for example, should we allow research on stem cells taken from human embryos, sex selection, or cloning? – and committees set up to advise on the ethical, social, and legal aspects of these questions often recommend legislation to prohibit the activity in question, or to allow it to be practiced under some form of regulation. Discussing a question at the level of law and public policy, however, raises somewhat different considerations than a discussion of personal ethics, because the consequences of adopting a public policy generally have much wider ramifications than the consequences of a personal choice. That is why some healthcare professionals feel justified in assisting a terminally ill patient to die, while at the same time opposing the legalization of physician‐assisted suicide. Paradoxical as this position may appear – and it is certainly open to criticism – it is not straightforwardly inconsistent.

      Many of the essays we have selected reflect the times in which they were written. Since bioethics often comments on developments in fast‐moving areas of medicine and the biological sciences, the factual content of articles in bioethics can become obsolete quite rapidly. In preparing this 4th edition, we have taken the opportunity to cover some new issues and to include some more recent writings. Part X, on Disability, is new, as are the section in Part VII on Academic Freedom and Research and the essays in Part IX on Doctors’ Duty to Treat. There are new articles in almost every other section as well, on gene editing, the morality of ending the lives of newborns, brain death, the eligibility of mentally ill patients for assisted dying and experiments on humans and on animals, and on public health.

      Some authors of articles that have become dated in their facts have kindly updated them especially for this edition. An article may, however, be dated in its facts but make ethical points that are still valid, or worth considering, so we have not excluded older articles for this reason.

      Helga Kuhse was a co‐editor of the first three editions of this anthology. She has now retired from academic work, and so decided not to join us in co‐editing this edition. Nevertheless, her influence remains present, in the articles carried over from earlier editions. We thank her for helping to establish Bioethics: An Anthology as a comprehensive and widely used collection of the best articles in the field.

      Katherine Carr did a stellar job as the copy‐editor of this volume. The number of errors she spotted in previously published peer‐reviewed (and presumably copy‐edited and proof‐read) journal articles is extraordinary.

      Last, but not least, we thank two Graduate Students in the Queen’s University Department of Philosophy who assisted us in sourcing possible materials for inclusion in the 3rd edition of this text (Nikoo Najand) and in this current edition (Chris Zajner).

      Notes

      1 1 See Van Rensselaer Potter, Bioethics: Bridge to the Future (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice‐Hall, 1971).

      2 2