Группа авторов

Bioethics


Скачать книгу

very significant contributions to science, the idea does not seem especially plausible. In the first place, whether an individual will turn out to do highly creative work, rather than being determined simply by his or her genetic makeup, surely depends upon traits whose acquisition is a matter either of the environment in which the individual grows up, or, alternatively, in view of Pinker’s point, of the prenatal wiring of that person’s brain.

      I am inclined to think, then, that there are problems with the present suggestion in the form in which it is usually put. On the other hand, I'm not convinced that a slightly more modest version cannot be sustained. Consider, for example, the chess‐playing Polgár sisters, where the father of three girls succeeded in creating an environment in which all three of his daughters became very strong chess players, with one of them – Judit Polgár – becoming the strongest female chess player who has ever lived. Is it not reasonable to think that if one were to make a number of clones of Judit Polgár, and then raised them in an environment very similar to that in which the Polgár sisters were raised, the result would be a number of very strong chess players?

      More generally, there is strong evidence of a very significant hereditary basis for intelligence, as Bouchard (1997, 55–6) and many others have argued, and it may well be that the right combination of heredity and environment plays a significant role in the development of other traits that may play a crucial role in creativity – traits such as extreme persistence, determination, and confidence in one's own abilities. So while the chance that the clone of an outstandingly creative individual will also achieve very great things is perhaps, at least in many areas, not especially high, I think that there is reason for thinking that, given an appropriate environment, the result in a number of areas may well turn out to be an individual who is likely to accomplish things that may benefit society in significant ways.

       3.3.8 furthering scientific knowledge: Psychology, the causes of traits of character, and the rearing of children

      A crucial theoretical task for psychology is the construction of a satisfactory theory to explain the acquisition of traits of character, and central to the development of such a theory is information about the extent to which various traits are (a) inherited, (b) dependent upon aspects of the environment that are controllable, or (c) dependent upon factors, either in the brain, or in the environment, that have a chancy quality. Such knowledge, however, is not just theoretically crucial to psychology. Knowledge of the contributions that are, and are not, made to the individual's development by his or her genetic makeup, by the prenatal state of the individual’s brain, by the environment in which he or she matures, and by chance events, will enable one to develop approaches to childrearing that will increase, at least to some extent, the likelihood that one can raise children with desirable traits, and thus people who will have a better chance of realizing their potentials, and of leading happy and satisfying lives. So this knowledge is not merely of great theoretical interest: it is also potentially very beneficial to society.

      I have argued both that there are no sound objections to cloning for scientific research or therapeutic purposes, or to the creation of human organ banks, and also that the cloning of persons is both desirable in various ways and, in principle, morally unproblematic.

      1 Annas, George J. (1998). “Why We Should Ban Human Cloning,” The New England Journal of Medicine, July 9, 1998.

      2 Bouchard, Thomas J., Jr. ( 1997). “Whenever the Twain Shall Meet,” The Sciences 37/5, September/October 1997, 52–7.

      3 Brock, Dan W. (1998). “Cloning Human Beings: An Assessment of the Ethical Issues Pro and Con.” In Martha C. Nussbaum and Cass R. Sunstein (eds.), Clones and Clones, New York: W. W. Norton and Company.

      4 Cerva, R. P. and Stojkovic, M. (2007). “Human embryonic stem cell derivation and nuclear transfer: impact on regenerative therapeutics and drug discovery,” Clinical Pharmacology & Therapeutics, 82/3, 310–15.

      5 Eisenberg Leon (1976). “The Outcome as Cause: Predestination and Human Cloning,” The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 1, 318–31.

      6 Feinberg, Joel (1980). “The Child's Right to an Open Future.” In W. Aiken and H. LaFollette, Whose Child? Children's Rights, Parental Authority, and State Power, Totowa, NJ: Rowan and Littlefield.

      7 Gallop Poll (2019). “Gay and Lesbian Rights”, https://news.gallup.com/poll/1651/gay‐lesbian‐rights.aspx (Accessed January 24, 2020.)

      8 GLAPN (2007). “History of Sodomy Laws,” http://www.glapn.org/sodomylaws/history/history.htm (Accessed September 17, 2020).

      9 Grogan, David (1990). “To Save Their Daughter from Leukemia, Abe and Mary Ayala Conceived a Plan‐and a Baby, People, March 5, 1990. https://people.com/archive/to‐save‐their‐daughter‐from‐leukemia‐abe‐and‐mary‐ayala‐conceived‐a‐plan‐and‐a‐baby‐vol‐33‐no‐9/ (Accessed January 24, 2020.)

      10 Harris, Judith Rich (1998). The Nurture Assumption, New York: Free Press.

      11 Hart, Ronald, Angelo Turturro, and Julian Leakey, ( 1997). “Born Again?” The Sciences 37/5, September/October 1997, 47–51.

      12 Jonas, Hans (1974). Philosophical Essay: From Ancient Creed to Technological Man, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice‐Hall.

      13 Kaczor, Christopher (2014). The Ethics of Abortion – Women’s Rights, Human Life, and